Acyclic model
In algebraic topology, a discipline within mathematics, the acyclic models theorem can be used to show that two homology theories are isomorphic. The theorem was developed by topologists Samuel Eilenberg and Saunders MacLane. They discovered that, when topologists were writing proofs to establish equivalence of various homology theories, there were numerous similarities in the processes. Eilenberg and MacLane then discovered the theorem to generalize this process.
It can be used to prove the Eilenberg–Zilber theorem.
Statement of the theorem
Let be an arbitrary category and
be the category of chain complexes of
-modules. Let
be covariant functors such that:
-
for
.
- There are
for
such that
has a basis in
, so
is a free functor.
-
is
- and
-acyclic at these models, which means that
for all
and all
.
Then the following assertions hold:
- Every natural transformation
is induced by a natural chain map
.
- If
are natural transformations,
are natural chain maps as before and
for all models
, then there is a natural chain homotopy between
and
.
- In particular the chain map
is unique up to natural chain homotopy.[1]
Generalizations
Projective and acyclic complexes
What is above is one of the earliest versions of the theorem. Another
version is the one that says that if is a complex of
projectives in an abelian category and
is an acyclic
complex in that category, then any map
extends to a chain map
, unique up to
homotopy.
This specializes almost to the above theorem if one uses the functor category as the abelian category. Free functors are projective objects in that category. The morphisms in the functor category are natural transformations, so the constructed chain maps and homotopies are all natural. The difference is that in the above version,
being acyclic is a stronger assumption than being acyclic only at certain objects.
On the other hand, the above version almost implies this version by letting a category with only one object. Then the free functor
is basically just free (and hence projective) module.
being acyclic at the models (there is only one) means nothing else than that the complex
is acyclic.
Acyclic classes
Then there is the grand theorem that unifies them all. Let be an abelian category (for example
or
). A class
of chain complexes over
will be called an acyclic class provided:
- The 0 complex is in
.
- The complex
belongs to
if and only if the suspension of
does.
- If the complexes
and
are homotopic and
, then
.
- Every complex in
is acyclic.
- If
is a double complex, all of whose rows are in
, then the total complex of
belongs to
.
There are three natural examples of acyclic classes, although doubtless others exist. The first is that of homotopy contractible complexes. The second is that of acyclic complexes. In functor categories (e.g. the category of all functors from topological spaces to abelian groups), there is a class of complexes that are contractible on each object, but where the contractions might not be given by natural transformations. Another example is again in functor categories but this time the complexes are acyclic only at certain objects.
Let denote the class of chain maps between complexes
whose mapping cone belongs to
. Although
does not necessarily have a calculus of either right
or left fractions, it has weaker properties of having homotopy classes
of both left and right fractions that permit forming the class
gotten by inverting the arrows in
.
Let be an augmented endofunctor on
,
meaning there is given a natural transformation
(the identity functor on
). We say that the chain complex
is
-presentable if for each
, the chain
complex
belongs to . The boundary operator is given by
.
We say that the chain complex functor is
-acyclic if the augmented chain complex
belongs to
.
Theorem. Let be an acyclic class and
the corresponding class of arrows in the category of
chain complexes. Suppose that
is
-presentable and
is
-acyclic.
Then any natural transformation
extends, in the category
to a natural
transformation of chain functors
and this is
unique in
up to chain homotopies.
If we suppose, in addition, that
is
-presentable, that
is
-acyclic, and that
is an isomorphism, then
is homotopy equivalence.
Example
Here is an example of this last theorem in action. Let
be the category of triangulable spaces and
be the
category of abelian group valued functors on
. Let
be the singular chain complex functor and
be the simplicial chain complex functor. Let
be the functor that assigns to each space
the
space
. Here,
is the
-simplex and this functor assigns to
the sum of as many copies of each
-simplex as there are maps
.
Then let
be defined by
. There is an
obvious augmentation
and this induces one on
. It can be shown that both
and
are both
-presentable and
-acyclic (the proof that
is not entirely
straightforward and uses a detour through simplicial subdivision, which
can also be handled using the above theorem). The class
is the class of homology equivalences. It is rather
obvious that
and so we conclude that
singular and simplicial homology are isomorphic on
.
There are many other examples in both algebra and topology, some of which are described in M. Barr, Acyclic Models. AMS, 2002.
References
- ↑ Dold, Albrecht (1980), Lectures on Algebraic Topology, A Series of Comprehensive Studies in Mathematics 200 (2nd ed.), Berlin, New York: Springer-Verlag, ISBN 3-540-10369-4
- Schon, R. Acyclic models and excision. _Proc. Amer. Math. Soc._ 59~(1) (1976) 167--168.