Causal structure
In mathematical physics, the causal structure of a Lorentzian manifold describes the causal relationships between points in the manifold.
Introduction
In modern physics (especially general relativity) spacetime is represented by a Lorentzian manifold. The causal relations between points in the manifold are interpreted as describing which events in spacetime can influence which other events.
Minkowski spacetime is a simple example of a Lorentzian manifold. The causal relationships between points in Minkowski spacetime take a particularly simple form since the space is flat. See Causal structure of Minkowski spacetime for more information.
The causal structure of an arbitrary (possibly curved) Lorentzian manifold is made more complicated by the presence of curvature. Discussions of the causal structure for such manifolds must be phrased in terms of smooth curves joining pairs of points. Conditions on the tangent vectors of the curves then define the causal relationships.
Tangent vectors
If is a Lorentzian manifold (for metric
on manifold
) then the tangent vectors at each point in the manifold can be classed into three different types.
A tangent vector
is
- timelike if
- null or lightlike if
- spacelike if
(Here we use the metric signature). A tangent vector is called "non-spacelike" if it is null or timelike.
These names come from the simpler case of Minkowski spacetime (see Causal structure of Minkowski spacetime).
Time-orientability
At each point in the timelike tangent vectors in the point's tangent space can be divided into two classes. To do this we first define an equivalence relation on pairs of timelike tangent vectors.
If and
are two timelike tangent vectors at a point we say that
and
are equivalent (written
) if
.
There are then two equivalence classes which between them contain all timelike tangent vectors at the point. We can (arbitrarily) call one of these equivalence classes "future-directed" and call the other "past-directed". Physically this designation of the two classes of future- and past-directed timelike vectors corresponds to a choice of an arrow of time at the point. The future- and past-directed designations can be extended to null vectors at a point by continuity.
A Lorentzian manifold is time-orientable[1] if a continuous designation of future-directed and past-directed for non-spacelike vectors can be made over the entire manifold.
Curves
A path in is a continuous map
where
is a nondegenerate interval (i.e., a connected set containing more than one point) in
. A smooth path has
differentiable an appropriate number of times (typically
), and a regular path has nonvanishing derivative.
A curve in is the image of a path or, more properly, an equivalence class of path-images related by re-parametrisation, i.e. homeomorphisms or diffeomorphisms of
. When
is time-orientable, the curve is oriented if the parameter change is required to be monotonic.
Smooth regular curves (or paths) in can be classified depending on their tangent vectors. Such a curve is
- chronological (or timelike) if the tangent vector is timelike at all points in the curve.
- null if the tangent vector is null at all points in the curve.
- spacelike if the tangent vector is spacelike at all points in the curve.
- causal (or non-spacelike) if the tangent vector is timelike or null at all points in the curve.
The requirements of regularity and nondegeneracy of ensure that closed causal curves (such as those consisting of a single point) are not automatically admitted by all spacetimes.
If the manifold is time-orientable then the non-spacelike curves can further be classified depending on their orientation with respect to time.
A chronological, null or causal curve in is
- future-directed if, for every point in the curve, the tangent vector is future-directed.
- past-directed if, for every point in the curve, the tangent vector is past-directed.
These definitions only apply to causal (chronological or null) curves because only timelike or null tangent vectors can be assigned an orientation with respect to time.
- A closed timelike curve is a closed curve which is everywhere future-directed timelike (or everywhere past-directed timelike).
- A closed null curve is a closed curve which is everywhere future-directed null (or everywhere past-directed null).
- The holonomy of the ratio of the rate of change of the affine parameter around a closed null geodesic is the redshift factor.
Causal relations
There are two types of causal relations between points and
in the manifold
.
-
chronologically precedes
(often denoted
) if there exists a future-directed chronological (timelike) curve from
to
.
-
strictly causally precedes
(often denoted
) if there exists a future-directed causal (non-spacelike) curve from
to
.
-
causally precedes
(often denoted
or
) if
strictly causally precedes
or
.
-
horismos
[2] (often denoted
or
) if
and
.
These relations are transitive:[3]
-
,
implies
-
,
implies
and satisfy[3]
-
implies
(this follows trivially from the definition)
-
,
implies
-
,
implies
For a point in the manifold
we define[3]
- The chronological future of
, denoted
, as the set of all points
in
such that
chronologically precedes
:
- The chronological past of
, denoted
, as the set of all points
in
such that
chronologically precedes
:
We similarly define
- The causal future (also called the absolute future) of
, denoted
, as the set of all points
in
such that
causally precedes
:
- The causal past (also called the absolute past) of
, denoted
, as the set of all points
in
such that
causally precedes
:
Points contained in , for example, can be reached from
by a future-directed timelike curve.
The point
can be reached, for example, from points contained in
by a future-directed non-spacelike curve.
As a simple example, in Minkowski spacetime the set is the interior of the future light cone at
. The set
is the full future light cone at
, including the cone itself.
These sets
defined for all
in
, are collectively called the causal structure of
.
For two subsets of
we define
- The chronological future of
relative to
,
, is the chronological future of
considered as a submanifold of
. Note that this is quite a different concept from
which gives the set of points in
which can be reached by future-directed timelike curves starting from
. In the first case the curves must lie in
in the second case they do not. See Hawking and Ellis.
- The causal future of
relative to
,
, is the causal future of
considered as a submanifold of
. Note that this is quite a different concept from
which gives the set of points in
which can be reached by future-directed causal curves starting from
. In the first case the curves must lie in
in the second case they do not. See Hawking and Ellis.
- A future set is a set closed under chronological future.
- A past set is a set closed under chronological past.
- An indecomposable past set is a past set which isn't the union of two different open past proper subsets.
-
is a proper indecomposable past set (PIP).
- A terminal indecomposable past set (TIP) is an IP which isn't a PIP.
- The future Cauchy development of
,
is the set of all points
for which every past directed inextendible causal curve through
intersects
at least once. Similarly for the past Cauchy development. The Cauchy development is the union of the future and past Cauchy developments. Cauchy developments are important for the study of determinism.
- A subset
is achronal if there do not exist
such that
, or equivalently, if
is disjoint from
.
- A Cauchy surface is an closed achronal set whose Cauchy development is
.
- A metric is globally hyperbolic if it can be foliated by Cauchy surfaces.
- The chronology violating set is the set of points through which closed timelike curves pass.
- The causality violating set is the set of points through which closed causal curves pass.
- For a causal curve
, the causal diamond is
(here we are using the looser definition of 'curve' whereon it is just a set of points). In words: the causal diamond of a particle's world-line
is the set of all events that lie in both the past of some point in
and the future of some point in
.
Properties
See Penrose, p13.
- A point
is in
if and only if
is in
.
-
-
-
-
- The horismos is generated by null geodesic congruences.
Topological properties:
-
is open for all points
in
.
-
is open for all subsets
.
-
for all subsets
. Here
is the closure of a subset
.
-
Conformal geometry
Two metrics and
are conformally related[4] if
for some real function
called the conformal factor. (See conformal map).
Looking at the definitions of which tangent vectors are timelike, null and spacelike we see they remain unchanged if we use or
As an example suppose
is a timelike tangent vector with respect to the
metric. This means that
. We then have that
so
is a timelike tangent vector with respect to the
too.
It follows from this that the causal structure of a Lorentzian manifold is unaffected by a conformal transformation.
See also
- Causal dynamical triangulation (CDT)
- Causality conditions
- Cauchy surface
- Closed timelike curve
- Globally hyperbolic manifold
- Lorentzian manifold
- Penrose diagram
- Spacetime
Notes
- ↑ Hawking & Israel 1979, p. 255
- ↑ Penrose 1972, p. 15
- 1 2 3 4 Penrose 1972, p. 12
- ↑ Hawking & Ellis 1973, p. 42
References
- Hawking, S.W.; Ellis, G.F.R. (1973), The Large Scale Structure of Space-Time, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, ISBN 0-521-20016-4
- Hawking, S.W.; Israel, W. (1979), General Relativity, an Einstein Centenary Survey, Cambridge University Press, ISBN 0-521-22285-0
- Penrose, R. (1972), Techniques of Differential Topology in Relativity, SIAM, ISBN 0898710057
Further reading
- G. W. Gibbons, S. N. Solodukhin; The Geometry of Small Causal Diamonds arXiv:hep-th/0703098 (Causal intervals)
- S.W. Hawking, A.R. King, P.J. McCarthy; A new topology for curved space–time which incorporates the causal, differential, and conformal structures; J. Math. Phys. 17 2:174-181 (1976); (Geometry, Causal Structure)
- A.V. Levichev; Prescribing the conformal geometry of a lorentz manifold by means of its causal structure; Soviet Math. Dokl. 35:452-455, (1987); (Geometry, Causal Structure)
- D. Malament; The class of continuous timelike curves determines the topology of spacetime; J. Math. Phys. 18 7:1399-1404 (1977); (Geometry, Causal Structure)
- A.A. Robb ; A theory of time and space; Cambridge University Press, 1914; (Geometry, Causal Structure)
- A.A. Robb ; The absolute relations of time and space; Cambridge University Press, 1921; (Geometry, Causal Structure)
- A.A. Robb ; Geometry of Time and Space; Cambridge University Press, 1936; (Geometry, Causal Structure)
- R.D. Sorkin, E. Woolgar; A Causal Order for Spacetimes with C^0 Lorentzian Metrics: Proof of Compactness of the Space of Causal Curves; Classical & Quantum Gravity 13: 1971-1994 (1996); arXiv:gr-qc/9508018 (Causal Structure)
External links
- Turing Machine Causal Networks by Enrique Zeleny, the Wolfram Demonstrations Project
- Weisstein, Eric W., "Causal Network", MathWorld.