Fair division of a single homogeneous resource

Fair division of a single homogeneous resource is one of the simplest settings in fair division problems. There is a single resource that should be divided between several people. The challenge is that each person derives a different utility from each amount of the resource. Hence, there are several conflicting principles for deciding how the resource should be divided. A primary conflict is between efficiency and equality. Efficiency is represented by the utilitarian rule, which maximizes the sum of utilities; equality is represented by the egalitarian rule, which maximizes the minimum utility. [1]:sub.2.5

Setting

In a certain society, there are:

This setting can have various interpretations. For example:[1]:44

In any case, the society has to decide how to divide the resource among the agents: it has to find a vector y_1,\dots,y_n such that: y_1+\cdots+y_n = t

Allocation rules

Envy-free

The Envy-freeness rule says that the resource should be allocated such that no agent envies another agent. In the case of a single homogeneous resource, it always selects the allocation that gives each agent the same amount of the resource, regardless of their utility function:

\forall i: y_i = t/n

Utilitarian

The utilitarian rule says that the sum of utilities should be maximized. Therefore the utilitarian allocation is:

y = \arg\max_y \sum_i u_i(y_i)

Egalitarian

The egalitarian rule says that the utilities of all agents should be equal. Therefore, we would like to select an allocation that satisfies:

\forall i,j: u_i(y_i) = u_j(y_j)

However, such allocation may not exist, since the ranges of the utility functions might not overlap (see example below). To ensure that a solution exists, we allow different utility levels, but require that agents with utility levels above the minimum receive no resources:

y_i>0 \implies u_i(y_i) = \min_j u_j(y_j)

Equivalently, the egalitarian allocation maximizes the minimum utility:

y = \arg\max_y \min_i u_i(y_i)

The utilitarian and egalitarian rules may lead to the same allocation or to different allocations, depending on the utility functions. Some examples are illustrated below.

Examples

Common utility and unequal endowments

Suppose all agents have the same utility function, u, but each agent i has a different initial endowment, x_i. So the utility of each agent i is given by:

u_i(y_i) = u(x_i + y_i)

If u is a concave function, representing diminishing returns, then the utilitarian and egalitarian allocations are the same - trying to equalize the endowments of the agents. For example, if there are 3 agents with initial endowments x=2,4,9 and the total amount is t=8, then both rules recommend the allocation y=5,3,0, since it both pushes towards equal utilities (as much as possible) and maximizes the sum of utilities.

In contrast, if u is a convex function, representing increasing returns, then the egalitarian allocation still pushes towards equality, but the utilitarian allocation now gives all the endowment to the richest agent: y=0,0,9. [1]:45 This makes sense, for example, when the resource is a scarce medication: it may be socially best to give all medication to the patient with the highest chances of curing.

Constant utility ratios

Suppose there is a common utility function u, but each agent has a different coefficient a_i representing this agent's productivity. So the utility of each agent i is given by:

u_i(y_i) = a_i\cdot u(y_i)

Here, the utilitarian and egalitarian approaches are diametrically opposed.[1]:46-47

Properties of allocation rules

See also

References

  1. 1 2 3 4 5 Herve Moulin (2004). Fair Division and Collective Welfare. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press. ISBN 9780262134231.
This article is issued from Wikipedia - version of the Tuesday, April 19, 2016. The text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution/Share Alike but additional terms may apply for the media files.