Hermarchus

For the genus of stick insects, see Hermarchus (genus).
Hermarchus

Hermarchus or Hermarch (Greek: Ἕρμαρχoς, Hermarkhos, "reign of Hermes"; c. 325-c. 250 BC[1]), sometimes incorrectly written Hermachus (Greek: Ἕρμαχoς, Hermakhos), was an Epicurean philosopher. He was the disciple and successor of Epicurus as head of the school. None of his writings survive. He wrote works directed against Plato, Aristotle, and Empedocles. A fragment from his Against Empedocles, preserved by Porphyry, discusses the need for law in society. His views on the nature of the gods are quoted by Philodemus.

Life

Hermarchus was a son of Agemarchus, a poor man of Mytilene (in insular Greece), and was at first brought up as a rhetorician, but afterwards became a faithful disciple of Epicurus, who left to him his garden, and appointed him his successor as the head of his school, about 270 BC.[2] He died in the house of Lysias at an advanced age, and left behind him the reputation of a great philosopher. Cicero has preserved a letter of Epicurus addressed to him.[3]

Writings

Hermarchus was the author of several works, which are characterised by Diogenes Laërtius[4] as "excellent" (Greek: κάλλιστα):

All of these works are lost, and we know nothing about them but their titles.[5] But from an expression of Cicero,[6] we may infer that his works were of a polemical nature, and directed against the philosophy of Plato and Aristotle, and on Empedocles.[7]

A long fragment (quotation or paraphrase) from an unspecified work of Hermarchus' has been preserved by Porphyry.[8] This fragment is probably from his Against Empedocles.[9] In this fragment, Hermarchus discusses the reasons for punishment for murder. He argues that early law-makers were guided by the principle that murder was not good for society, and were able to educate other people that this was a rational principle. They then created punishments for those people who could not be educated. For everyone who understood that murder was not useful, laws would not be needed; punishments are only needed for those who fail to understand this. For Hermarchus, this was an example of social progress and an increase in rationality.[10]

Philodemus in his On the Way of Life of the Gods,[11] quotes the view of Hermarchus that the gods breathe, because the gods are living beings and all living things breathe.[12] Philodemus goes on to say that, according to Hermarchus, the gods must talk to one another, because conversation is conducive to happiness:

And one must say that they use speech and converse with one another; for, he [Hermarchus] says, we would not consider them more fortunate and indestructible if they did not, but rather similar to mute human beings. For since in fact all of us who are not maimed make use of language, to say that the gods either are maimed or do not resemble us in this respect (there being no other way either they or we could give shape to utterances) is extremely foolish, especially since conversation with those like themselves is a source of indescribable pleasure to the good.[13]

Notes

  1. Dorandi, Tiziano (1999). "Chapter 2: Chronology". In Algra, Keimpe; et al. The Cambridge History of Hellenistic Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. 51–52. ISBN 9780521250283.
  2.  Laërtius, Diogenes (1925). "Epicurus". Lives of the Eminent Philosophers 2:10. Translated by Hicks, Robert Drew (Two volume ed.). Loeb Classical Library. § 17, 24.
  3. Cicero, De Finibus, ii. 30
  4. Laërtius 1925, § 24.
  5. A small papyrus fragment showing the title of his "Against Empedocles", was actually found at Oxyrhynchus, POxy 3318
  6. Cicero, De Natura Deorum, i. 33
  7. Cicero, Academica, ii. 30; Athenaeus, Deipnosophistae, xiii. 53; Photius, Bibliotheca, 167.
  8. Porphyry, De Abstinentia i. 7-12; 26
  9. Catherine Osborne, (2007), Dumb Beasts and Dead Philosophers: Humanity and the Humane in Ancient Philosophy and Literature, page 202. Oxford University Press.
  10. A. A. Long, (2006), From Epicurus to Epictetus: Studies in Hellenistic and Roman Philosophy, pages 196-7. Oxford University Press.
  11. PHerc 152/7
  12. Keimpe Algra, (1999), The Cambridge History of Hellenistic Philosophy, page 456. Cambridge University Press
  13. Philodemus quoted in Michael Wigodsky, Emotions and Immortality in Philodemus "On the Gods" and the "Aeneid". in David Armstrong, Vergil, Philodemus, and the Augustans, page 219. (2004). University of Texas Press
This article is issued from Wikipedia - version of the Saturday, March 26, 2016. The text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution/Share Alike but additional terms may apply for the media files.