Leslie Armour

Leslie Armour (9 March 1931 – 1 November 2014) was a Canadian-born philosopher and writer on social economics. He is the father of the cellist and impresario Julian Armour.[1]

Academic career

Armour completed a BA at the University of British Columbia in 1952 and a PhD at the University of London in 1956. He is a fellow of the Royal Society of Canada and a Research Professor of Philosophy at the Dominican University College, Ottawa, Adjunct Professor of Philosophical Theology at St. Paul University, and Emeritus Professor of Philosophy at the University of Ottawa. He has taught at universities in Montana, California, and Ohio. Since 2004 he has been editor of the International Journal of Social Economics. His current areas of study include metaphysics, epistemology, philosophy, and the philosophical underpinnings of economics and "he is a pioneer in publishing early Canadian philosophy and has philosophical publications in metaphysics, religion, law, politics and economics".[2] Armour has contributed significantly to the interdisciplinary school of Canadian Studies.

He has authored nine books (three with co-authors), more than seventy chapters in books and a hundred articles in scholarly journals. He is also a frequent speaker at conferences on economics, religious studies and French and German philosophy.[3] There is a bibliography to 2001 and extensive commentaries on Armour's work in William Sweet's Idealism, Metaphysics, and Community.[4]

Inference and Persuasion

Armour's most recent book, Inference and Persuasion: An Introduction to Logic and Critical Reasoning (2005), was co-authored by Richard Feist. It is written so as to be accessible to all audiences and is concerned with the problems associated with logic, offering suggestions rather than solutions, for, as Armour states, nothing is certain. This book discusses meaning-assignment, rule-making, beliefs, and the correlation between belief and action. It pays special attention to how these are misunderstood, corrupted and blocked so that we are robbed of our freedom.[5] The authors argue that reason and experience are both important to logic, and that logic is important because it allows for understanding and survival.[6]

Inference is described as the beliefs and judgments that create rules. Inference and rule are tools that we use for freedom. We think for ourselves and draw our own conclusions; knowledge permits freedom to act. Yet the way inferences are drawn is subject to the influence of logicians, such as Aristotle, and their language.[7] Aristotle's focus on class inclusion and exclusion highlights the limits of the language of logic. This idea of classification is problematic, as it ignores things not included in a class and the fact that the meaning of classes is not clear.[8] "Trying to lay out axioms or rules in advance... will always lead to limitations" because "imposing systems on our thinking seems to bring limits into play".[9]

Examining John Dewey's logic (Chapter Four), the notion that reason and experience are interconnected is evident. Logic is concerned with the 'human world', which is not the 'world in itself'.[10] Thinking has a purpose; it is a problem solving tool, an attempt to make experience coherent.[11]

The authors go through previous theories and views on logic and add interesting and thought-provoking ideas. They note the tensions between experience and logic, the biases associated with reasoning,[12] and the importance of context.[13] In "Logic and Morality" it is argued that our biases inform how we form our understanding of facts. How we reason about what to do is based on practicality, which is based on our values. In "Logic and Politics" we see the notion of classes, as assembled from members, as individualist, with community interests ignored. The authors suggest we must understand the world through relationships, since individuals only exist in context, such as social contexts. Logic has the tendency to either ignore social realities or create individualist societies.[14]

Concluding their text with the limits set by the rules of logic, they state that the ultimate reason for caution in using logic is that "One should not let one's choice of logic impose restrictions on one's freedom — provided of course that one can see rational alternatives. Where that line is drawn readers must decide for themselves"[15]

Accomplishments

Armour was elected to the Royal Society of Canada in August 1998, which recognized his significant contribution to research and scholarly work.[16]

Publications

Armour has also published some 200 papers in learned journals and chapters in books.

References

  1. "Leslie Armour Obituary". The Ottawa Citizen. 7 November 2014. Retrieved 25 June 2015.
  2. "Armour, Leslie", The Canadian Encyclopedia.
  3. "Armour, Leslie", The Canadian Encyclopedia.
  4. William Sweet, ed., Idealism, Metaphysics, and Community, Ashgate, 2001
  5. Armour and Feist, Inference and Persuasion, p. 14
  6. Inference and Persuasion, Preface
  7. Inference and Persuasion, pp. 1–22
  8. Inference and Persuasion, pp. 18–22
  9. Inference and Persuasion, p. 51
  10. Inference and Persuasion, p. 54
  11. Inference and Persuasion, pp. 54–5
  12. "Logic and Morality", Inference and Persuasion
  13. "Logic and Politics", Inference and Persuasion
  14. Inference and Persuasion, pp. 193–8
  15. Inference and Persuasion, p. 209
  16. Centre Stage, August 1998

Canadian Who's Who

External links

This article is issued from Wikipedia - version of the Wednesday, April 20, 2016. The text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution/Share Alike but additional terms may apply for the media files.