Megarian school
The Megarian school of philosophy, which flourished in the 4th century BC, was founded by Euclid of Megara, one of the pupils of Socrates. Its ethical teachings were derived from Socrates, recognizing a single good, which was apparently combined with the Eleatic doctrine of Unity. Some of Euclid's successors developed logic to such an extent that they became a separate school, known as the Dialectical school. Their work on modal logic, logical conditionals, and propositional logic played an important role in the development of logic in antiquity.
History
The Megarian school of philosophy was founded by Euclid of Megara, who had been one of the pupils of Socrates in the late 5th century BC.[1] His successors, as head of the school in Megara, were said to have been Ichthyas (mid 4th century BC), and Stilpo (late 4th century BC).[2] It is unlikely, however, that the Megarian school was a genuine institution, nor did it have a unified philosophical position.[3] It was said that the philosophers of the school were first called Megarians and that later they were called Eristics, and then Dialecticians,[4] but it is probable that these names designated splinter groups distinct from the Megarian school.[5] Besides Ichthyas, Euclid's most important pupils were Eubulides of Miletus[6] and Clinomachus of Thurii.[7] It seems to have been under Clinomachus that a separate Dialectical school was founded,[8] which placed great emphasis on logic and dialectic, and Clinomachus was said to have been "the first to write about propositions and predicates."[7] However, Euclid himself taught logic,[9] and his pupil, Eubulides, who was famous for employing celebrated paradoxes,[6] was the teacher of several later dialecticians.
Via Stilpo, the Megarian school is said to have influenced the Eretrian school under Menedemus and Asclepiades, but the biggest influence was on Stoicism. Zeno, the founder of the Stoic school, was said to have studied under Stilpo and Diodorus Cronus,[10] and to have disputed with Philo the Dialectician. It was perhaps the Dialecticians, Diodorus and Philo, who were the biggest influence on the development of Stoic logic, and that Zeno studied under Stilpo to learn his moral teachings, although Stilpo, too, is said to have excelled "in the invention of arguments and in sophistry."[2]
Philosophy
Euclid had been a pupil of Socrates, but ancient historians also regarded him as a successor to the Eleatics, hence his philosophy was seen as a fusion of Eleatic and Socratic thought. Thus the Eleatic idea of "The One" was identified with the Socratic "Form of the Good,"[11] and the opposite of Good was regarded by Euclid as non-existent.[4] But the emphasis of his thought is not on being but on the good, and idea that what is opposite to the good does not exist arises from the understanding of the good's unity.[12] This theme is typically Socratic, what matters is the moral good and the will of the good person to strive towards it. Stilpo is said to have continued the Eleatic tendency, by asserting a strict monism and denying all change and motion,[13] and he also rejected Plato's Theory of Forms.[14] In ethics, Stilpo taught freedom, self-control, and self-sufficiency, approaching the teachings of the Cynics, another Socratic school.[15]
Besides studying logical puzzles and paradoxes, the Dialecticians made two important logical innovations, by re-examining modal logic, and by starting an important debate on the nature of conditional statements.[16] This was the work of Diodorus Cronus and Philo the Dialectician, the only two members of the Dialectical school we have detailed information about. Through their development of propositional logic, the Dialectical school played an important role in the development of logic, which was an important precursor of Stoic logic.
See also
Notes
- ↑ Diogenes Laërtius, ii. 47
- 1 2 Diogenes Laërtius, ii. 113
- ↑ Gill & Pellegrin 2006, p. 132
- 1 2 Diogenes Laërtius, ii. 106
- ↑ O'Toole & Jennings 2004, p. 406
- 1 2 Diogenes Laërtius, ii. 108
- 1 2 Diogenes Laërtius, ii. 112
- ↑ O'Toole & Jennings 2004, p. 406 Although the name "Dialectical school" was apparently coined by Dionysius of Chalcedon, (Diogenes Laërtius, ii. 106)
- ↑ Diogenes Laërtius, ii. 107
- ↑ Diogenes Laërtius, vii. 16
- ↑ Diogenes Laërtius, ii. 106; Cicero, Academica, ii. 42
- ↑ Gill & Pellegrin 2006, p. 134
- ↑ Aristocles, in Eusebius, Praeparatio Evangelica xiv. 16. 1
- ↑ Diogenes Laërtius, ii. 119
- ↑ Goulet-Cazé 1996, pp. 403–4
- ↑ Kneale & Kneale 1984, p. 119
References
- Gill, Mary Louise; Pellegrin, Pierre (2006), A Companion to Ancient Philosophy, Blackwell
- Goulet-Cazé, Marie-Odile (1996), "A Comprehensive Catalogue of Known Cynic Philosophers", in Bracht Branham, R.; Goulet-Cazé, Marie-Odile, The Cynics: The Cynic Movement in Antiquity and Its Legacy, University of California Press
- Kneale, William; Kneale, Martha (1984), The Development of Logic, Oxford University Press
- O'Toole, Robert R.; Jennings, Raymond E. (2004), "The Megarians and the Stoics", in Gabbay, Dov; Woods, John, Handbook of the History of Logic: Greek, Indian, and Arabic logic, North Holland, ISBN 0-444-50466-4
External links
Wikisource has the text of the 1911 Encyclopædia Britannica article Megarian School of Philosophy. |
- Dialectical School entry by Susanne Bobzien in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
- The Dialectical School and the Origin of Propositional Logic with an annotated bibliography
- "Megarians". Catholic Encyclopedia. New York: Robert Appleton Company. 1913.
|
|