Minority interpretations of quantum mechanics
There is a diversity of views that propose interpretations of quantum mechanics. They vary in how many physicists accept or reject them. An interpretation of quantum mechanics is a conceptual scheme that proposes to relate the mathematical formalism to the physical phenomena of interest. The present article is about those interpretations which, independently of their intrinsic value, remain today less known, or are simply less debated by the scientific community, for different reasons.
History
The historical dichotomy between the "orthodox" Copenhagen interpretation and "unorthodox" minority views developed in the 1950s debate surrounding Bohmian mechanics.
During most of the 20th century, collapse theories were clearly the mainstream view, and the question of interpretation of quantum mechanics mostly revolved around how to interpret "collapse. Proponents of either "pilot-wave" (de Broglie-Bohm-like) or "many-worlds" (Everettian) interpretations tend to emphasize how their respective camps were intellectually marginalized throughout 1950s to 1980s. In this (historical) sense, all non-collapse theories are (historically) "minority" interpretations.
The term 'Copenhagen interpretation' suggests some definite set of rules for interpreting the mathematical formalism of quantum mechanics. However, no such text exists, apart from some informal popular lectures by Bohr and Heisenberg, which contradict each other on several important issues. It appears that the term "Copenhagen interpretation", with its more definite sense, was coined by Heisenberg in the 1950s,[1] while criticizing "unorthodox" interpretations such as that of David Bohm.[2][3][4] Before the book was released for sale, Heisenberg privately expressed regret for having used the term, due to its suggestion of the existence of other interpretations, that he considered to be "nonsense".[5]
Since the 1990s, there has been a resurgence of interest in non-collapse theories. Interpretations of quantum mechanics now mostly fall into the categories of collapse theories (including the Copenhagen interpretation), hidden variables ("Bohm-like"), many-worlds ("Everettian") and quantum information approaches. While collapse theories continue to be seen as the default or mainstream position, there is no longer any clear dichotomy between "orthodox" and "unorthodox" views.
Some of the historically relevant approaches to quantum mechanics have now themselves become "minority interpretations", or widely seen as obsolete. In this sense, there is a variety of reasons for why a specific approach may be considered marginal: because it is a very specialized sub-variant of a more widely known class of interpretations, because it is seen as obsolete (in spite of possible historical significance), because it is a very recent suggestion that has not received wide attention, or because it is rejected as flawed.
As a rough guide to a picture of what are the relevant "minority" views, consider the "snapshot" of opinions collected in a poll by Schlosshauer et al. at the 2011 "Quantum Physics and the Nature of Reality" conference of July 2011.[6] The authors reference a similarly informal poll carried out by Max Tegmark at the "Fundamental Problems in Quantum Theory" conference in August 1997. In both polls, the Copenhagen interpretation received the largest number of votes. In Tegmark's poll, many-worlds interpretations came in second place, while in the 2011 poll, many-worlds was at third place (18%), behind quantum information approaches in second place (24%). Other options given as "interpretation of quantum mechanics" in the 2011 poll were: objective collapse theories (9% support), Quantum Bayesianism (6% support) and Relational quantum mechanics (6% support), besides consistent histories, de Broglie–Bohm theory, modal interpretation, ensemble interpretation and transactional interpretation which received no votes.
Classes of interpretations
The Stanford Encyclopedia as of 2015 groups interpretations of quantum mechanics into five classes (all of which contain further divisions):
- "Bohmian mechanics" (pilot-wave theories),[7]
- "collapse theories",[8]
- "many-worlds interpretations",[9]
- "modal interpretation"[10]
- "relational interpretations"[11]
List of interpretations
Collapse theories
- von Neumann–Wigner interpretation ("consciousness causes collapse"), mostly historical
- Objective collapse theory: these are extensions of quantum mechanics rather than "interpretations" in the narrow sense.
Many-worlds
"Everettian" (many-worlds) interpretations as a whole were long a "minority" field in general, but they are now a major contender of the mainstream collapse approach.
- Many-minds interpretation (Zeh 1970)
- Cosmological Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics (Aguirre and Tegmark 2010)[12]
Hidden variables
"Bohm-like" (hidden variable) theories as a whole are a "minority view" as compared to collapse (Copenhagen) or many-worlds (Everettian) interpretations.
- Popper's experiment[13]
- Stochastic interpretation
- Time-symmetric interpretations [14][15][16][17][18][19]
- the Calogero conjecture (Francesco Calogero) suggests the classical stochastic background field to which Edward Nelson attributes quantum mechanical behavior in his theory of stochastic quantization is a fluctuating space-time, and that there are further mathematical relations between the involved quantities.
- Transactional interpretation
- Zitterbewegung interpretation
- Elementary cycles, based on space-time recurrences are imposed as semiclassical quantization conditions, similarly to the quantization of a particle in a box. The resulting cyclic mechanics are formally equivalent to both the canonical formulation and Feynman formulation of quantum mechanics,[20][21][22] It is an evolution of the Bohr-Sommerfeld quantization or the zitterbewegung and suggests that quantum mechanics emerges as statistical description of extremely fast periodic dynamics, as proposed by 't Hooft Determinism.[23] The idea has originated applications in modern physics, such as a geometrical description of gauge invariance [24] and an interpretation of the Maldacena duality.[25]
Quantum information
- Quantum Bayesianism
- Hidden-measurements interpretation, a realistic interpretation of quantum mechanics based on a condition of lack of knowledge about which specific measurement-interaction takes place (i.e., is actualized) each time a measurement is executed.[26][27]
- Relational quantum mechanics treats the state of a quantum system as being observer-dependent, that is, the state is the relation between the observer and the system. This interpretation was first delineated by Carlo Rovelli in 1994. It uses some ideas from Wheeler on quantum information.[28]
Other
- Elementary space-time cycles, is a theory based on space-time recurrences are imposed as semiclassical quantization conditions, similarly to the quantization of a particle in a box. The resulting cyclic mechanics are formally equivalent to both the canonical formulation and Feynman formulation of quantum mechanics,[29][30][31] It is an evolution of the Bohr-Sommerfeld quantization or the zitterbewegung and suggests that quantum mechanics emerges as statistical description of extremely fast periodic dynamics, as proposed by 't Hooft Determinism.[32] The idea has originated applications in modern physics, such as a geometrical description of gauge invariance [33] and an interpretation of the Maldacena duality.[34]
- The ensemble interpretation, or statistical interpretation can be viewed as a minimalist approach;[35] The wave function in this interpretation is not a property of any individual system, it is by its nature a statistical description of a hypothetical "ensemble" of similar systems. This is the interpretation historically advocated by Albert Einstein.[36]
- Modal interpretation (van Fraassen 1972)[37] Van Fraassen's proposal is "modal" because it leads to a modal logic of quantum propositions. Since the 1980s, a number of authors have developed other "realist" proposals which can in retrospect be classed with van Fraassen's "modal" proposal.
- Consistent histories (Dowker and Kent 1995),[38] based on a consistency criterion that then allows probabilities to be assigned to various alternative histories of a system.
- "Montevideo interpretation" (Gambini and Pullin 2009),[39][40] suggesting that quantum gravity makes for fundamental limitations on the accuracy of clocks, which imply a type of decoherence.[41]
- "Pondicherry interpretation" (Mohrhoff 2000–2005),[42] based on the idea of objective probability and "supervenience of the microscopic on the macroscopic".[43]
- Synchronized Chaos Interpretation (Duane 2001)[44][45]
- Theory of Incomplete Measurements (de Dinechin 2012)[46]
- "Växjö Interpretation" (Khrennikov 2012), "combination of realism on the subquantum level with nonobjectivity of quantum observables"[47]
- London (Ticker Tape) Interpretation (O'Kane 2012)[48]
- Dimensional Theory (Nikkhah Shirazi 2012)[49]
- Intrinsic Quantum State Interpretation (Mamas 2013)[50]
See also
- Interpretation of quantum mechanics (list of more mainstream theories)
References
- ↑ Howard, Don (2004). "Who invented the Copenhagen Interpretation? A study in mythology". Philosophy of Science 71: 669–682. doi:10.1086/425941. JSTOR 10.1086/425941.
- ↑ Bohm, David (1952). "A Suggested Interpretation of the Quantum Theory in Terms of "Hidden" Variables. I & II". Physical Review 85 (2): 166–193. Bibcode:1952PhRv...85..166B. doi:10.1103/PhysRev.85.166.
- ↑ H. Kragh, Quantum generations: A History of Physics in the Twentieth Century, Princeton University Press, 1999, p. 210. ("the term 'Copenhagen interpretation' was not used in the 1930s but first entered the physicist’s vocabulary in 1955 when Heisenberg used it in criticizing certain unorthodox interpretations of quantum mechanics.")
- ↑ Lectures with the titles 'The Copenhagen Interpretation of Quantum Theory' and 'Criticisms and Counterproposals to the Copenhagen Interpretation', that Heisenberg delivered in 1955, are reprinted in the collection Physics and Philosophy.
- ↑ Olival Freire Jr., "Science and exile: David Bohm, the hot times of the Cold War, and his struggle for a new interpretation of quantum mechanics", Historical Studies on the Physical and Biological Sciences, Volume 36, Number 1, 2005, pp. 31–35. ("I avow that the term ‘Copenhagen interpretation’ is not happy since it could suggest that there are other interpretations, like Bohm assumes. We agree, of course, that the other interpretations are nonsense, and I believe that this is clear in my book, and in previous papers. Anyway, I cannot now, unfortunately, change the book since the printing began enough time ago.")
- ↑ Schlosshauer, Maximilian; Kofler, Johannes; Zeilinger, Anton (2013-01-06). "A Snapshot of Foundational Attitudes Toward Quantum Mechanics". Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 44 (3): 222–230. arXiv:1301.1069. doi:10.1016/j.shpsb.2013.04.004.
- ↑ Goldstein, Sheldon, "Bohmian Mechanics", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2013 Edition).
- ↑ Ghirardi, Giancarlo, "Collapse Theories", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2011 Edition).
- ↑ Vaidman, Lev, "Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2015 Edition)
- ↑ Lombardi, Olimpia and Dieks, Dennis, "Modal Interpretations of Quantum Mechanics", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2014 Edition).
- ↑ Laudisa, Federico and Rovelli, Carlo, "Relational Quantum Mechanics", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2013 Edition)
- ↑ ’’Born in an Infinite Universe: a Cosmological Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics”, A. Aguirre and M. Tegmark (2010) arXiv:1008.1066
- ↑ Combourieu, Marie-Christine; Popper, Karl R. (1992). "About the EPR controversy". Foundations of Physics 22 (10): 1303–1323. doi:10.1007/bf01889715.
- ↑ Watanabe, Satosi. "Symmetry of physical laws. Part III. Prediction and retrodiction." Reviews of Modern Physics 27.2 (1955): 179.
- ↑ Davidon, W.C. "Quantum Physics of Single Systems." Il Nuovo Cimento, Volume 36B, pp. 34-40 (1976).
- ↑ Aharonov, Y. and Vaidman, L. "On the Two-State Vector Reformulation of Quantum Mechanics." Physica Scripta, Volume T76, pp. 85-92 (1998).
- ↑ Wharton, K. B. "Time-Symmetric Quantum Mechanics." Foundations of Physics, 37(1), pp. 159-168 (2007).
- ↑ Wharton, K. B. "A Novel Interpretation of the Klein-Gordon Equation." Foundations of Physics, 40(3), pp. 313-332 (2010).
- ↑ Heaney, M. B. "A Symmetrical Interpretation of the Klein-Gordon Equation." Foundations of Physics (2013): http://link.springer.com/article/10.1007%2Fs10701-013-9713-9.
- ↑ Dolce, D "Compact Time and Determinism for Bosons: foundations", Foundations of Physics, 41, pp. 178-203 (2011) Donatello Dolce (2010). "Compact Time and Determinism for Bosons: Foundations". Foundations of Physics 41 (2): 178–203. arXiv:0903.3680. Bibcode:2010FoPh..tmp...86D. doi:10.1007/s10701-010-9485-4.
- ↑ Dolce, D,; "Elementary spacetime cycles", Eur. Phys. Lett. 102, 31002 (2013), arXiv:1305.2802v1
- ↑ Dolce, D "On the intrinsically cyclic nature of space-time in elementary particles", J. Phys.: Conf. Ser. 343 (2012) 012031 Donatello Dolce (2012). "On the intrinsically cyclic nature of space-time in elementary particles". J.Phys.Conf.Ser. 343: 012031. arXiv:1206.1140. Bibcode:2012JPhCS.343a2031D. doi:10.1088/1742-6596/343/1/012031.
- ↑ 't Hooft, G "The mathematical basis for deterministic quantum mechanics", DOI:10.1088/1742-6596/67/1/012015, arxiv=quant-ph/0604008
- ↑ Dolce, D "Gauge Interaction as Periodicity Modulation", Annals of Physics, Volume 327, Issue 6, June 2012, pp. 1562–1592 Donatello Dolce (2012). "Gauge Interaction as Periodicity Modulation". Annals of Physics 327 (6): 1562–1592. arXiv:1110.0315. Bibcode:2012AnPhy.327.1562D. doi:10.1016/j.aop.2012.02.007.
- ↑ Dolce, D "Classical geometry to quantum behavior correspondence in a Virtual Extra Dimension", Annals #of Physics, Volume 327, Issue 9, September 2012, pp 2354–2387 Donatello Dolce (2012). "Classical geometry to quantum behavior correspondence in a Virtual Extra Dimension". Annals of Physics 327 (9): 2354–2387. arXiv:1110.0316. Bibcode:2012AnPhy.327.2354D. doi:10.1016/j.aop.2012.06.001.
- ↑ Aerts, D. (1986). A possible explanation for the probabilities of quantum mechanics, Journal of Mathematical Physics, 27, pp. 202-210.
- ↑ Aerts, D. and Sassoli de Bianchi, M. (2014). The extended Bloch representation of quantum mechanics and the hidden-measurement solution to the measurement problem. Annals of Physics 351, Pages 975–1025 (Open Access).
- ↑ Wheeler, J. A.: "Information, physics, quantum: The search for links"; in Zurek,W., ed.: "Complexity, Entropy and the Physics of Information"; pp 3–28; Addison-Wesley; 1990, p. 3.
- ↑ Dolce, D "Compact Time and Determinism for Bosons: foundations", Foundations of Physics, 41, pp. 178-203 (2011) Donatello Dolce (2010). "Compact Time and Determinism for Bosons: Foundations". Foundations of Physics 41 (2): 178–203. arXiv:0903.3680. Bibcode:2010FoPh..tmp...86D. doi:10.1007/s10701-010-9485-4.
- ↑ Dolce, D,; "Elementary spacetime cycles", Eur. Phys. Lett. 102, 31002 (2013), arXiv:1305.2802v1
- ↑ Dolce, D "On the intrinsically cyclic nature of space-time in elementary particles", J. Phys.: Conf. Ser. 343 (2012) 012031 Donatello Dolce (2012). "On the intrinsically cyclic nature of space-time in elementary particles". J.Phys.Conf.Ser. 343: 012031. arXiv:1206.1140. Bibcode:2012JPhCS.343a2031D. doi:10.1088/1742-6596/343/1/012031.
- ↑ 't Hooft, G "The mathematical basis for deterministic quantum mechanics", DOI:10.1088/1742-6596/67/1/012015, arxiv=quant-ph/0604008
- ↑ Dolce, D "Gauge Interaction as Periodicity Modulation", Annals of Physics, Volume 327, Issue 6, June 2012, pp. 1562–1592 Donatello Dolce (2012). "Gauge Interaction as Periodicity Modulation". Annals of Physics 327 (6): 1562–1592. arXiv:1110.0315. Bibcode:2012AnPhy.327.1562D. doi:10.1016/j.aop.2012.02.007.
- ↑ Dolce, D "Classical geometry to quantum behavior correspondence in a Virtual Extra Dimension", Annals #of Physics, Volume 327, Issue 9, September 2012, pp 2354–2387 Donatello Dolce (2012). "Classical geometry to quantum behavior correspondence in a Virtual Extra Dimension". Annals of Physics 327 (9): 2354–2387. arXiv:1110.0316. Bibcode:2012AnPhy.327.2354D. doi:10.1016/j.aop.2012.06.001.
- ↑ "The statistical interpretation of quantum mechanics" (PDF). Nobel Lecture. December 11, 1954.
- ↑ "The attempt to conceive the quantum-theoretical description as the complete description of the individual systems leads to unnatural theoretical interpretations, which become immediately unnecessary if one accepts the interpretation that the description refers to ensembles of systems and not to individual systems." Einstein: Philosopher-Scientist, ed. P.A. Schilpp (Harper & Row, New York)
- ↑ Olimpia Lombardi, Dennis Dieks (2012). "Modal Interpretations of Quantum Mechanics". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- ↑ F. Dowker and A. Kent, "Properties of Consistent Histories", Phys. Rev. Lett. 75, 3038 - 3041 (1995)
- ↑ Gambini, Rodolfo; Pullin, Jorge (2009). "The Montevideo interpretation of quantum mechanics: frequently asked questions". Journal of Physics: Conference Series 174: 012003. arXiv:0905.4402. Bibcode:2009JPhCS.174a2003G. doi:10.1088/1742-6596/174/1/012003.
- ↑ Jorge Pullin. "The Montevideo Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics". Retrieved April 2012.
- ↑ Jeremy Butterfield, Assessing the Montevideo Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics (2014) arXiv:1406.4351v1
- ↑ Mohrhoff, U. (2005). "The Pondicherry interpretation of quantum mechanics: An overview". Pramana 64 (2): 171–185. arXiv:quant-ph/0412182. Bibcode:2005Prama..64..171M. doi:10.1007/BF02704872.
- ↑ Afshin Shafieea, Maryam Jafar-Aghdamib, Mehdi Golshanic, 'A critique of Mohrhoff's interpretation of quantum mechanics', Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Volume 37, Issue 2, June 2006, 316–329
- ↑ Duane, G.S., 2001: Violation of Bell's inequality in synchronized hyperchaos, Found. Phys. Lett., 14, 341-353.
- ↑ Duane, G.S., 2005: Quantum nonlocality from synchronized chaos, Int. J. Theor. Phys., 44, 1917-1932.
- ↑ Christophe de Dinechin. "Theory of Incomplete Measurements" (PDF). Retrieved April 2012.
- ↑ Khrennikov, Andrei (2012). "Vaxjo Interpretation of Wave Function:2012". AIP Conf. Proc. 1508: 242–252. arXiv:1210.2390. doi:10.1063/1.4773136.
- ↑ Shaun O’Kane (1997). "London (Ticker Tape) Interpretation" (PDF). Retrieved April 2012.
- ↑ Nikkhah Shirazi, Armin (2012). "A Novel Approach to 'Making Sense' out of the Copenhagen Interpretation". AIP Conf. Proc. 1508: 422–427. doi:10.1063/1.4773159.
- ↑ Mamas, D.L., An intrinsic quantum state interpretation of quantum mechanics, Physics Essays 26, 181–182 (2013)