Moral authority

Moral authority is authority premised on principles, or fundamental truths, which are independent of written, or positive, laws. As such, moral authority necessitates the existence of and adherence to truth. Because truth does not change, the principles of moral authority are immutable or unchangeable, although as applied to individual circumstances the dictates of moral authority for action may vary due to the exigencies of human life. These principles, which can be of metaphysical and/or religious nature, are considered normative for behavior, whether they are or are not also embodied in written laws,[1] and even if the community is ignoring or violating them.[2] Therefore, the authoritativeness or force of moral authority is applied to the conscience of each individual, who is free to act according to or against its dictates.

Moral authority has thus also been defined as the "fundamental assumptions that guide our perceptions of the world".[3]

Characteristics

An individual or a body of people who are seen as communicators of such principles but which does not have the physical power to enforce them on the unwilling are spoken of as having moral authority. An example is the Catholic Church.[4]

In this sense, moral authority has been defined as "the capacity to convince others how the world should be", as opposed to epistemic authority, "the capacity to convince others of how the world is".[5]

Changing focuses

Since the Age of Enlightenment, traditional sources of moral authority such as church or state have been viewed with increasing suspicion in Western culture:[6] perhaps indeed all claims to moral authority.[7] Instead of guides, entertainers; in place of ideals, stimulation.[8]

Expertise, or alternatively what Emmanuel Levinas called the tyranny of opinion,[9] or else an appeal to science,[10] may be looked to for alternative sources of moral authority; or there may be a postmodern revulsion from all grand narratives which might ground such narratives [11] in favour of moral relativism.

Where a figure still wields some degree of moral authority, this may be attributed in large part to his modernist reticence, lack of dogma, and capacity for self-doubt[12] - as opposed for example to the unchallenged moral authority for centuries attributed to Virgil as a norma vivendi.[13]

In reaction to the erosion of sources of moral authority, Late Modernity has also seen the appearance of various forms of fundamentalism, from a range of religious types to market fundamentalism.[14]

See also

Look up moral authority in Wiktionary, the free dictionary.

References

  1. Legal Definitions: Moral Authority
  2. Richard Norris, Timothy F. Sedgwick, The Business of All Believers: Reflections on Leadership (Church Publishing, Inc. 2009 ISBN 978-1-59627119-7), p. 86
  3. James Davison Hunter, Culture Wars (Basic Books 1992 ISBN 978-0-46501534-4), p. 119
  4. Full text of Veritas Splendor, English Translation. John Paul II. August 6, 1993
  5. Jay A. Labinger, "Individual or Institutional Authority in Science?"
  6. S. Sims ed., The Routledge Companion to Postmodernism (2012) p. 219
  7. Niamh Stephenson, Theoretical Psychology (2003) p. 5
  8. Ivo Mosley, Dumbing Down (2000) p. 107
  9. Stephenson, p. 9
  10. T. L. Brown, Imperfect Oracle (2009) p. 7
  11. Sims, p. 253
  12. Bernard O'Donoghue ed., The Cambridge Companion to Seamus Heaney (2009) p. 11 and p. 69
  13. M. Tudeau-Clayton, Jonson, Shakespeare and Early Modern Virgil (1998) p. 26 and p. 72-7
  14. Sims, p. 272
This article is issued from Wikipedia - version of the Wednesday, April 13, 2016. The text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution/Share Alike but additional terms may apply for the media files.