Neutral theory of molecular evolution

For the monograph by Kimura, see The Neutral Theory of Molecular Evolution.

The neutral theory of molecular evolution holds that at the molecular level most evolutionary changes and most of the variation within and between species is not caused by natural selection but by genetic drift of mutant alleles that are neutral. A neutral mutation is one that does not affect an organism's ability to survive and reproduce. The neutral theory allows for the possibility that most mutations are deleterious, but holds that because these are rapidly purged by natural selection, they do not make significant contributions to variation within and between species at the molecular level. Mutations that are not deleterious are assumed to be mostly neutral rather than beneficial. In addition to assuming the primacy of neutral mutations, the theory also assumes that the fate of neutral mutations is determined by the sampling processes described by specific models of random genetic drift.[1]

According to Motoo Kimura, the theory applies only for evolution at the molecular level, and phenotypic evolution is controlled by natural selection, as postulated by Charles Darwin. The proposal of the neutral theory was followed by an extensive "neutralist-selectionist" controversy over the interpretation of patterns of molecular divergence and polymorphism, peaking in the 1970s and 1980s. The controversy is still unsettled among evolutionary biologists.

Overview

While some scientists, such as Freese (1962) [2] and Freese and Yoshida (1965),[3] had suggested that neutral mutations were probably widespread, a coherent theory of neutral evolution was proposed by Motoo Kimura in 1968,[4] and by King and Jukes independently in 1969.[5]

Kimura, King, and Jukes suggested that when one compares the genomes of existing species, the vast majority of molecular differences are selectively "neutral", i.e. the molecular changes represented by these differences do not influence the fitness of organisms. As a result, the theory regards these genomic features as neither subject to, nor explicable by, natural selection. This view is based in part on the degenerate genetic code, in which sequences of three nucleotides (codons) may differ and yet encode the same amino acid (GCC and GCA both encode alanine, for example). Consequently, many potential single-nucleotide changes are in effect "silent" or "unexpressed" (see synonymous or silent substitution). Such changes are presumed to have little or no biological effect.

A second hypothesis of the neutral theory is that most evolutionary change is the result of genetic drift acting on neutral alleles, rather than for example genetic hitchhiking of a neutral allele due to genetic linkage with non-neutral alleles. After appearing by mutation, a neutral allele may become more common within the population via genetic drift. Usually, it will be lost, or in rare cases it may become fixed, meaning that the new allele becomes standard in the population. This stochastic process is assumed to obey equations describing random genetic drift by means of accidents of sampling.

According to the neutral theory, mutations appear at rate μ in each of the 2N copies of a gene, and fix with probability 1/(2N). This means that if all mutations were neutral, the rate at which fixed differences accumulate between divergent populations is predicted to be equal to the per-individual mutation rate, e.g. during errors in DNA replication; both are equal to μ. When the proportion of mutations that are neutral is constant, so is the divergence rate between populations. This provides a rationale for the molecular clock, although the discovery of a molecular clock predated neutral theory.[6]

Many molecular biologists and population geneticists also contributed to the development of the neutral theory, which is different from the neo-Darwinian theory.[1][7][8]

Neutral theory does not deny the occurrence of natural selection. Hughes writes: "Evolutionary biologists typically distinguish two main types of natural selection: purifying selection, which acts to eliminate deleterious mutations; and positive (Darwinian) selection, which favors advantageous mutations. Positive selection can, in turn, be further subdivided into directional selection, which tends toward fixation of an advantageous allele, and balancing selection, which maintains a polymorphism. The neutral theory of molecular evolution predicts that purifying selection is ubiquitous, but that both forms of positive selection are rare, whereas not denying the importance of positive selection in the origin of adaptations."[9] In another essay, Hughes writes: "Purifying selection is the norm in the evolution of protein coding genes. Positive selection is a relative rarity but of great interest, precisely because it represents a departure from the norm."[10] A more general and more recent view of molecular evolution is presented by Nei.[8]

The "neutralist–selectionist" debate

A heated debate arose when Kimura's theory was published, largely revolving around the relative percentages of alleles that are "neutral" versus "non-neutral" in any given genome. Contrary to the perception of many onlookers, the debate was not about whether natural selection does occur. Kimura argued that molecular evolution is dominated by selectively neutral evolution but at the phenotypic level, changes in characters were probably dominated by natural selection rather than genetic drift.[11]

Tomoko Ohta emphasized the importance of nearly neutral mutations, in particularly slightly deleterious mutations.[12] The population dynamics of nearly neutral mutations is essentially the same as that of neutral mutations unless the absolute magnitude of the selection coefficient is greater than 1/N, where N is the effective population size with respect to selection.[1][7][8] The value of N may therefore affect how many mutations can be treated as neutral and how many as deleterious.

There are a large number of statistical methods for testing whether neutral theory is a good description of evolution (e.g., McDonald-Kreitman test [13]), and many authors claimed detection of selection (Fay et al. 2002,[14] Begun et al. 2007,[15] Shapiro et al. 2007,[16] Hahn 2008,[17] Akey 2009.[18]). However, Nei et al. (2010).[19] have argued that their methods for claiming so depend on many assumptions which are not biologically justified.

See also

References

  1. 1 2 3 Kimura, Motoo. (1983). The neutral theory of molecular evolution. Cambridge
  2. Freese, E. (1962). On the evolution of base composition of DNA. J THeor Biol, 3:82-101.
  3. Freese, E. and Yoshida, A. (1965). The role of mutations in evolution. In V Bryson, and H J Vogel, eds. Evolving Genes and Proteins, pp. 341-55. Academic, New York.
  4. Kimura M. (1968). Evolutionary Rate at the Molecular Level. Nature 217:624-6.
  5. King JL, Jukes TH. (1969). Non-Darwinian Evolution. Science 164:788-97.
  6. Zuckerkandl, E. and Pauling, L.B. (1962). "Molecular disease, evolution, and genetic heterogeneity". In Kasha, M. and Pullman, B (editors). Horizons in Biochemistry. Academic Press, New York. pp. 189–225.
  7. 1 2 Nei, M. (2005). Selectionism and neutralism in molecular evolution. Mol Biol Evol, 22: 2318-42
  8. 1 2 3 Nei, M. (2013). Mutation-driven evolution. Oxford University Press, Oxford
  9. Hughes, Austin L. (2007). "Looking for Darwin in all the wrong places: the misguided quest for positive selection at the nucleotide sequence level". Heredity 99 (4): 364–373. doi:10.1038/sj.hdy.6801031. PMID 17622265.
  10. Hughes, Austin L. (2000). Adaptive Evolution of Genes and Genomes. Oxford University Press. p. 53. ISBN 0-19-511626-7.
  11. Provine (1991)
  12. Ohta, T. (2002). "Near-neutrality in evolution of genes and gene regulation". PNAS 99 (25): 16134–16137. doi:10.1073/pnas.252626899. PMC 138577. PMID 12461171.
  13. Kreitman, Martin (2000). "M D S P A H". Annual Review of Genomics and Human Genetics 1 (1): 539–559. doi:10.1146/annurev.genom.1.1.539. PMID 11701640.
  14. Fay, J. C., Wyckoff, G. J., and Wu, C. I. (2002). Testing the neutral theory of molecular evolution with genomic data from Drosophila. Nature, 415:1024-6
  15. Begun, D. J., Holloway, A. K., Stevens, K., Hillier, L. W., Poh, Y. P. et al. (2007). Population genomics: whole-genome analysis of polymorphism and divergence in Drosophila simulans. PLoS Biol, 5:e310.
  16. Shapiro J. A., Huang W., Zhang C., Hubisz M. J., Lu J. et al. 2007. Adaptive genic evolution in the Drosophila genomes. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 104:2271–76.
  17. Hahn, M.W. (2008). "Toward a selection theory of molecular evolution". Evolution 62: 255–265. doi:10.1111/j.1558-5646.2007.00308.x. PMID 18302709.
  18. Akey J. M. (2009). Constructing genomic maps of positive selection in humans: where do we go from here? Genome Res 19:711–22.
  19. Nei, M., Suzuki, Y., and M. Nozawa. (2010). The neutral theory of molecular evolution in the genomic era. Annu Rev Genom Hum Genet. 11:265-89.

External links

This article is issued from Wikipedia - version of the Tuesday, March 01, 2016. The text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution/Share Alike but additional terms may apply for the media files.