Overtaking criterion

In economics, the overtaking criterion is used to compare infinite streams of outcomes.

Often, the decisions of a policy-maker may have influences that extend to the far future. Economic decisions made today may influence the economic growth of a nation for an unknown number of years into the future. In such cases, it is often convenient to model the future outcomes as an infinite stream. Then, it may be required to compare two infinite streams and decide which one of them is better (for example, in order to decide on a policy). The overtaking criterion is one option to do this comparison.

Notation

X is the set of possible outcomes. E.g, it may be the set of positive real numbers, representing the possible annual gross domestic product. It is normalized

X^\infty is the set of infinite sequences of possible outcomes. Each element in X^\infty is of the form: x = (x_1,x_2,\ldots).

\preceq is a partial order. Given two infinite sequences x,y, it is possible that x is weakly better (x\succeq y) or that y is weakly better (y\succeq x) or that they are incomparable.

\prec is the strict variant of \preceq, i.e, x\prec y if x\preceq y and not y\preceq x.

Cardinal definition

\prec is called the "overtaking criterion" if there is an infinite sequence of real-valued functions u_1,u_2,\ldots: X\to \mathbb{R} such that:[1]

x\prec y      iff      \exists N_0: \forall N>N_0: \sum_{t=1}^N u_t(x_t) < \sum_{t=1}^N u_t(y_t)

An alternative condition is:[2][3]

x\prec y      iff      0 < \lim \inf_{T\to \infty} \sum_{t=1}^N u_t(x_t) - \sum_{t=1}^N u_t(y_t)

Examples:

1. In the following example, x\prec y:

x=(0,0,0,0,...)
y=(-1,2,0,0,...)

This shows that a difference in a single time period may affect the entire sequence.

2. In the following example, x and y are incomparable:

x = (4,1,4,4,1,4,4,1,4,\ldots)
y = (3,3,3,3,3,3,3,3,3,\ldots)

The partial sums of x are larger, then smaller, then equal to the partial sums of y, so none of these sequences "overtakes" the other.

This also shows that the overtaking criterion cannot be represented by a single cardinal utility function. I.e, there is no real-valued function U such that x\prec y iff U(x)<U(y). One way to see this is:[2] for every a,b\in\mathbb{R} and a<b:

(a,a,\ldots) \prec (a+1,a,\ldots) \prec (b,b,\ldots)

Hence, there is a set of disjoint nonempty segments in (X,\prec) with a cardinality like the cardinality of \mathbb{R}. In contrast, every set of disjoint nonempty segments in (\mathbb{R},\prec) must be a countable set.

Ordinal definition

Define X_T as the subset of X^\infty in which only the first T elements are nonzero. Each element of X_T is of the form (x_1,\ldots,x_T,0,0,0,\ldots).

\prec is called the "overtaking criterion" if it satisfies the following axioms:

1. For every T, \preceq is a complete order on X_T

2. For every T, \preceq is a continuous relation in the obvious topology on X_T.

3. For each T>1, X_T is preferentially-independent (see Debreu theorems#Additivity of ordinal utility function for a definition). Also, for every T\geq 3, at least three of the factors in X_T are essential (have an effect on the preferences).

4. x\prec y      iff      \exists T_0: \forall T>T_0: 
(x_1,\ldots,x_T,0,0,0,\ldots) \prec (y_1,\ldots,y_T,0,0,0,\ldots)

Every partial order that satisfies these axioms, also satisfies the first cardinal definition.[1]

As explained above, some sequences may be incomparable by the overtaking criterion. This is why the overtaking criterion is defined as a partial ordering on X^\infty, and a complete ordering only on X_T.

Applications

The overtaking criterion is used in economic growth theory.[4]

It is also used in repeated games theory, as an alternative to the limit-of-means criterion and the discounted-sum criterion. See Folk theorem (game theory)#Overtaking.[2][3]

See also

References

  1. 1 2 Brock, William A. (1970). "An Axiomatic Basis for the Ramsey-Weizsacker Overtaking Criterion". Econometrica 38 (6): 927. doi:10.2307/1909701. JSTOR 1909701.
  2. 1 2 3 Rubinstein, Ariel (1979). "Equilibrium in supergames with the overtaking criterion". Journal of Economic Theory 21: 1. doi:10.1016/0022-0531(79)90002-4.
  3. 1 2 Rubinstein, A. (1980). "Strong perfect equilibrium in supergames". International Journal of Game Theory 9: 1. doi:10.1007/BF01784792.
  4. See papers by: Gale, Koopmans, McKenzie and von Weizsacker
This article is issued from Wikipedia - version of the Tuesday, December 22, 2015. The text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution/Share Alike but additional terms may apply for the media files.