Polynomial conjoint measurement

Polynomial conjoint measurement is an extension of the theory of conjoint measurement to three or more attributes. It was initially developed by the mathematical psychologists David Krantz (1968) and Amos Tversky (1967). The theory was given a comprehensive mathematical exposition in the first volume of Foundations of Measurement (Krantz, Luce, Suppes & Tversky, 1971), which Krantz and Tversky wrote in collaboration with the mathematical psychologist R. Duncan Luce and philosopher Patrick Suppes. Krantz & Tversky (1971) also published a non-technical paper on polynomial conjoint measurement for behavioural scientists in the journal Psychological Review.

As with the theory of conjoint measurement, the significance of polynomial conjoint measurement lies in the quantification of natural attributes in the absence of concatenation operations. Polynomial conjoint measurement differs from the two attribute case discovered by Luce & Tukey (1964) in that more complex composition rules are involved.

Polynomial conjoint measurement

Krantz's (1968) schema

Most scientific theories involve more than just two attributes; and thus the two variable case of conjoint measurement has rather limited scope. Moreover, contrary to the theory of n - component conjoint measurement, many attributes are non-additive compositions of other attributes (Krantz, et al., 1971). Krantz (1968) proposed a general schema to ascertain the sufficient set of cancellation axioms for a class of polynomial combination rules he called simple polynomials. The formal definition of this schema given by Krantz, et al., (1971, p. 328) is as follows.

Let Y =\big\{y_1, y_2, \ldots, y_n \big\}. The set S\left(Y\right) is the smallest set of simple polynomials such that:

Informally, the schema argues: a) single attributes are simple polynomials; b) if G1 and G2 are simple polynomials that are disjoint (i.e. have no attributes in common), then G1 + G2 and G1 \times G2 are simple polynomials; and c) no polynomials are simple except as given by a) and b).

Let A, P and U be single disjoint attributes. From Krantz’s (1968) schema it follows that four classes of simple polynomials in three variables exist which contain a total of eight simple polynomials:

Krantz’s (1968) schema can be used to construct simple polynomials of greater numbers of attributes. For example, if D is a single variable disjoint to A, B, and C then three classes of simple polynomials in four variables are A + B + C + D, D + (B + AC) and D + ABC. This procedure can be employed for any finite number of variables. A simple test is that a simple polynomial can be ‘split’ into either a product or sum of two smaller, disjoint simple polynomials. These polynomials can be further ‘split’ until single variables are obtained. An expression not amenable to ‘splitting’ in this manner is not a simple polynomial (e.g. AB + BC + AC (Krantz & Tversky, 1971)).

Axioms

Let A = \big\{a, b, c, \ldots \big\}, P = \big\{p, q, r, \ldots \big\} and U = \big\{u, v, w, \ldots \big\} be non-empty and disjoint sets. Let " \succsim " be a simple order. Krantz et al. (1971) argued the quadruple Z = \langle A, P, U, \succsim \rangle is a polynomial conjoint system if and only if the following axioms hold.

\left(a, r, w\right)\succsim \left(c, s, v\right), \left(d, p, u\right)\succsim \left(b, t, x\right), \left(d, r, x\right)\succsim \left(e, s, u\right) and \left(c, t, y\right)\succsim \left(d, q, y\right) implies \left(a, p, v\right)\succsim \left(b, q, w\right) is true for all a, b, c, d, e\in A; p, q, r, s, t \in P and u, v, w, x, y\in U.

Representation theorems

The quadruple Z = \langle A, P, U, \succsim \rangle falls into one class of three variable simple polynomials by virtue of the joint single cancellation axiom.

References

This article is issued from Wikipedia - version of the Thursday, March 31, 2016. The text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution/Share Alike but additional terms may apply for the media files.