Proper morphism

In algebraic geometry, a proper morphism between schemes is an analog of a proper map between complex analytic spaces.

Some authors call a proper variety over a field k a complete variety. For example, every projective variety over a field k is proper over k. A scheme X of finite type over the complex numbers (for example, a variety) is proper over C if and only if the space X(C) of complex points with the classical (Euclidean) topology is compact and Hausdorff.

A closed immersion is proper. A morphism is finite if and only if it is proper and quasi-finite.

Definition

A morphism f: XY of schemes is called universally closed if for every scheme Z with a morphism ZY, the projection from the fiber product

X \times_Y Z \to Z

is a closed map of the underlying topological spaces. A morphism of schemes is called proper if it is separated, of finite type, and universally closed ([EGA] II, 5.4.1 ). One also says that X is proper over Y. In particular, a variety X over a field k is said to be proper over k if the morphism X → Spec(k) is proper.

Examples

For any natural number n, projective space Pn over a commutative ring R is proper over R. Projective morphisms are proper, but not all proper morphisms are projective. For example, there is a smooth proper complex variety of dimension 3 which is not projective over C.[1] Affine varieties of positive dimension over a field k are never proper over k. More generally, a proper affine morphism of schemes must be finite.[2] For example, it is not hard to see that the affine line A1 over a field k is not proper over k, because the morphism A1 → Spec(k) is not universally closed. Indeed, the pulled-back morphism

\mathbb{A}^1 \times_k \mathbb{A}^1 \to \mathbb{A}^1

(given by (x,y) ↦ y) is not closed, because the image of the closed subset xy = 1 in A1 × A1 = A2 is A1 − 0, which is not closed in A1.

Properties and characterizations of proper morphisms

In the following, let f: XY be a morphism of schemes.

Valuative criterion of properness

Valuative criterion of properness

There is a very intuitive criterion for properness which goes back to Chevalley. It is commonly called the valuative criterion of properness. Let f: XY be a morphism of finite type of noetherian schemes. Then f is proper if and only if for all discrete valuation rings R with fraction field K and for any K-valued point xX(K) that maps to a point f(x) that is defined over R, there is a unique lift of x to \overline{x} \in X(R). (EGA II, 7.3.8). Noting that Spec K is the generic point of Spec R and discrete valuation rings are precisely the regular local one-dimensional rings, one may rephrase the criterion: given a regular curve on Y (corresponding to the morphism s: Spec RY) and given a lift of the generic point of this curve to X, f is proper if and only if there is exactly one way to complete the curve.

Similarly, f is separated if and only if in every such diagram, there is at most one lift \overline{x} \in X(R).

For example, given the valuative criterion, it becomes easy to check that projective space Pn is proper over a field (or even over Z). One simply observes that for a discrete valuation ring R with fraction field K, every K-point [x0,...,xn] of projective space comes from an R-point, by scaling the coordinates so that all lie in R and at least one is a unit in R.

Proper morphism of formal schemes

Let f\colon \mathfrak{X} \to \mathfrak{S} be a morphism between locally noetherian formal schemes. We say f is proper or \mathfrak{X} is proper over \mathfrak{S} if (i) f is an adic morphism (i.e., maps the ideal of definition to the ideal of definition) and (ii) the induced map f_0\colon X_0 \to S_0 is proper, where X_0 = (\mathfrak{X}, \mathcal{O}_\mathfrak{X}/I), S_0 = (\mathfrak{S}, \mathcal{O}_\mathfrak{S}/K), I = f^*(K) \mathcal{O}_\mathfrak{X} and K is the ideal of definition of \mathfrak{S}.(EGA III, 3.4.1) The definition is independent of the choice of K.

For example, if g: YZ is a proper morphism of locally noetherian schemes, Z0 is a closed subset of Z, and Y0 is a closed subset of Y such that g(Y0) ⊂ Z0, then the morphism \widehat{g}\colon Y_{/Y_0} \to Z_{/Z_0} on formal completions is a proper morphism of formal schemes.

Grothendieck proved the coherence theorem in this setting. Namely, let f\colon \mathfrak{X} \to \mathfrak{S} be a proper morphism of locally noetherian formal schemes. If F is a coherent sheaf on \mathfrak{X}, then the higher direct images R^i f_* F are coherent.[11]

See also

References

  1. Hartshorne (1977), Appendix B, Example 3.4.1.
  2. Liu (2002), Lemma 3.3.17.
  3. Stacks Project, Tag 02YJ.
  4. Grothendieck, EGA IV, Part 4, Corollaire 18.12.4; Stacks Project, Tag 02LQ.
  5. Grothendieck, EGA IV, Part 3, Théorème 8.11.1.
  6. Stacks Project, Tag 01W0.
  7. Stacks Project, Tag 03GX.
  8. Grothendieck, EGA II, Corollaire 5.6.2.
  9. Conrad (2007), Theorem 4.1.
  10. SGA 1, XII Proposition 3.2.
  11. Grothendieck, EGA III, Part 1, Théorème 3.4.2.

External links

This article is issued from Wikipedia - version of the Tuesday, March 01, 2016. The text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution/Share Alike but additional terms may apply for the media files.