MÄ«mÄṃsÄ
Part of a series on | ||
Hindu philosophy | ||
---|---|---|
![]() | ||
Orthodox | ||
|
||
Heterodox | ||
|
||
|
||
Mimamsa (IAST: MÄ«mÄṃsÄ) is a Sanskrit word that means "reflection" or "critical investigation".[1][2] It is also the name of one of six orthodox (astika) schools of Hinduism. The school is known for its philosophical theories on the nature of dharma, based on hermeneutics of the Vedas.[3] The school was influential and foundational to the vedÄntic schools of Hinduism, with the difference that the MÄ«mÄṃsÄ school (also known as PÅ«rva-MÄ«mÄṃsÄ or Karma-MÄ«mÄṃsÄ[4]) developed and emphasized karma-kÄṇá¸a (study of ritual actions, early four Vedas), while the VedÄnta schools (also known as Uttara-MÄ«mÄṃsÄ) developed and emphasized jñana-kÄṇá¸a (study of knowledge and spirituality, later parts of Vedas, like the Upaniá¹£ads).[3]
MÄ«mÄṃsÄ has several sub-schools, each defined by its epistemology. The PrÄbhÄkara sub-school (from PrabhÄkara MiÅ›ra) considered five epistemically reliable means to gaining knowledge - Pratyaká¹£ha (perception), AnumÄna (inference), UpamÄna (comparison and analogy), ArthÄpatti (postulation, derivation from circumstances), and Åšabda (word, testimony of past or present reliable experts).[5][6] The BhÄá¹á¹a sub-school (from KumÄrila Bhaá¹á¹a) added a sixth to its canon of reliable epistemology - Anupalabdhi (non-perception, negative/cognitive proof).[5][7]
The school of MÄ«mÄṃsÄ consists of both atheistic and theistic doctrines and the school showed little interest in systematic examination of the existence of God. Rather, it held that the soul is an eternal, omnipresent, inherently active spiritual essence, then focussed on the epistemology and metaphysics of dharma.[4][8][9] To them, dharma meant rituals and social duties, not devas (gods) because gods existed only in name.[4] The MÄ«mÄṃsakas held that Vedas are "eternal authorless infallible", that Vedic vidhi (injunctions) and mantras in rituals are prescriptive kÄrya (actions), and the rituals are of primary importance and merit. They considered the Upaniá¹£ads (later portions of Vedas) and other self-knowledge, spirituality-related texts as subsidiary, a philosophical view that VedÄnta school of Hinduism disagreed with.[3][4]
MÄ«mÄṃsÄ gave rise to the study of philology and the philosophy of language.[10] While their deep analysis of language and linguistics influenced other schools of Hinduism,[11] their views were not shared by others. MÄ«mÄṃsakas considered the purpose and power of language was to clearly prescribe the proper, correct and right. In contrast, VedÄntins extended the scope and value of language as a tool to also describe, develop and derive.[4] MÄ«mÄṃsakas considered orderly, law driven, procedural life as central purpose and noblest necessity of dharma and society, and divine (theistic) sustenance means to that end.
The MÄ«mÄṃsÄ school of Hinduism is a form of realism.[12] A key text of the MÄ«mÄṃsÄ school is the MÄ«mÄṃsÄ SÅ«tra of Jaimini.[4][13]
Terminology
MÄ«mÄṃsÄ (Sanskrit: मीमांसा, also spelled Mimamsa) means "reflection, consideration, profound thought, investigation, examination, discussion" in Sanskrit.[14] It also refers to the "examination of the Vedic text"[14] and to a school of Hindu philosophy that is also known as PÅ«rva MÄ«mÄṃsÄ ("prior" inquiry, also Karma-MÄ«mÄṃsÄ), in contrast to Uttara MÄ«mÄṃsÄ ("posterior" inquiry, also Jñana-MÄ«mÄṃsÄ) – the opposing school of Vedanta. This division is based on classification of the Vedic texts into karmakÄṇá¸a, the early sections of the Veda treating of mantras and rituals (Samhitas and Brahmanas), and the jñÄnakÄṇá¸a dealing with the meditation, reflection and knowledge of Self, Oneness, Brahman (the Upanishads).[3][13] Between the Samhitas and Brahmanas, the Mimamsa school places greater emphasis to the Brahmanas - the part of Vedas that is a commentary on Vedic rituals.[15]
Donald Davis translates Mimamsa as the "desire to think", and in coloquial historical context as "how to think and interpret things".[16] In the last centuries of the 1st-millennium BCE, the word MÄ«mÄṃsÄ began to denote the thoughts on and interpretation of the Vedas, first as Purva-Mimamsa for rituals portions in the earlier layers of texts in the Vedas, and as Uttara-Mimamsa for the philosophical portions in the last layers.[16][17] Over time, Purva-Mimamsa was just known as the Mimamsa school, and the Uttara-Mimamsa as the Vedanta school.[17]
Epistemology
In the field of epistemology, later MimÄṃsÄkas made some notable contributions. Unlike the Nyaya or the Vaisheshika systems, the PrÄbhÄkara sub-school of MÄ«mÄṃsÄ recognizes five means of valid knowledge (Skt. pramÄṇa). The BhÄá¹á¹a sub-school of MÄ«mÄṃsÄ recognizes one additional sixth, namely anuapalabdhi, just like Advaita Vedanta school of Hinduism. These six epistemically reliable means of gaining knowledge are:
Pratyaksa
Main article : Pratyaksha
Pratyaká¹£a (पà¥à¤°à¤¤à¥à¤¯à¤•à¥à¤·à¤¾à¤¯) means perception. It is of two types in Mimamsa and other schools of Hinduism: external and internal. External perception is described as that arising from the interaction of five senses and worldly objects, while internal perception is described by this school as that of inner sense, the mind.[18][19] The ancient and medieval Indian texts identify four requirements for correct perception:[20] Indriyarthasannikarsa (direct experience by one's sensory organ(s) with the object, whatever is being studied), Avyapadesya (non-verbal; correct perception is not through hearsay, according to ancient Indian scholars, where one's sensory organ relies on accepting or rejecting someone else's perception), Avyabhicara (does not wander; correct perception does not change, nor is it the result of deception because one's sensory organ or means of observation is drifting, defective, suspect) and Vyavasayatmaka (definite; correct perception excludes judgments of doubt, either because of one's failure to observe all the details, or because one is mixing inference with observation and observing what one wants to observe, or not observing what one does not want to observe).[20] Some ancient scholars proposed "unusual perception" as pramana and called it internal perception, a proposal contested by other Indian scholars. The internal perception concepts included pratibha (intuition), samanyalaksanapratyaksa (a form of induction from perceived specifics to a universal), and jnanalaksanapratyaksa (a form of perception of prior processes and previous states of a 'topic of study' by observing its current state).[21] Further, some schools of Hinduism considered and refined rules of accepting uncertain knowledge from Pratyaká¹£a-pranama, so as to contrast nirnaya (definite judgment, conclusion) from anadhyavasaya (indefinite judgment).[22]
Anumana
Main article : Anumana
AnumÄṇa (अनà¥à¤®à¤¾à¤¨) means inference. It is described as reaching a new conclusion and truth from one or more observations and previous truths by applying reason.[23] Observing smoke and inferring fire is an example of Anumana.[18] In all except one Hindu philosophies,[24] this is a valid and useful means to knowledge. The method of inference is explained by Indian texts as consisting of three parts: pratijna (hypothesis), hetu (a reason), and drshtanta (examples).[25] The hypothesis must further be broken down into two parts, state the ancient Indian scholars: sadhya (that idea which needs to proven or disproven) and paksha (the object on which the sadhya is predicated). The inference is conditionally true if sapaksha (positive examples as evidence) are present, and if vipaksha (negative examples as counter-evidence) are absent. For rigor, the Indian philosophies also state further epistemic steps. For example, they demand Vyapti - the requirement that the hetu (reason) must necessarily and separately account for the inference in "all" cases, in both sapaksha and vipaksha.[25][26] A conditionally proven hypothesis is called a nigamana (conclusion).[27]
Upamana
Main article : Upamana
UpamÄṇa (उपमान) means comparison and analogy.[5][6] Some Hindu schools consider it as a proper means of knowledge.[28] Upamana, states Lochtefeld,[29] may be explained with the example of a traveller who has never visited lands or islands with endemic population of wildlife. He or she is told, by someone who has been there, that in those lands you see an animal that sort of looks like a cow, grazes like cow but is different from a cow in such and such way. Such use of analogy and comparison is, state the Indian epistemologists, a valid means of conditional knowledge, as it helps the traveller identify the new animal later.[29] The subject of comparison is formally called upameyam, the object of comparison is called upamanam, while the attribute(s) are identified as samanya.[30] Thus, explains Monier Williams, if a boy says "her face is like the moon in charmingness", "her face" is upameyam, the moon is upamanam, and charmingness is samanya. The 7th century text Bhaá¹á¹ikÄvya in verses 10.28 through 10.63 discusses many types of comparisons and analogies, identifying when this epistemic method is more useful and reliable, and when it is not.[30] In various ancient and medieval texts of Hinduism, 32 types of Upanama and their value in epistemology are debated.
Arthapatti
ArthÄpatti (अरà¥à¤¥à¤¾à¤ªà¤¤à¥à¤¤à¤¿) means postulation, derivation from circumstances.[5][6] In contemporary logic, this pramana is similar to circumstantial implication.[31] As example, if a person left in a boat on river earlier, and the time is now past the expected time of arrival, then the circumstances support the truth postulate that the person has arrived. Many Indian scholars considered this pramana as invalid or at best weak, because the boat may have gotten delayed or diverted.[32] However, in cases such as deriving the time of a future sunrise or sunset, this method was asserted by the proponents to be reliable. Another common example for arthapatti found in the texts of MÄ«mÄṃsÄ and other schools of Hinduism is, that if "Devadatta is fat" and "Devadatta does not eat in day", then the following must be true: "Devadatta eats in the night". This form of postulation and deriving from circumstances is, claim the Indian scholars, a means to discovery, proper insight and knowledge.[33] The Hindu schools that accept this means of knowledge state that this method is a valid means to conditional knowledge and truths about a subject and object in original premises or different premises. The schools that do not accept this method, state that postulation, extrapolation and circumstantial implication is either derivable from other pramanas or flawed means to correct knowledge, instead one must rely on direct perception or proper inference.[34]
Anupalabdi
Main article : Anupalabdhi, See also: Abhava
Anupalabdi (अनà¥à¤ªà¤²à¤¬à¥à¤§à¤¿), accepted only by Kumarila Bhatta sub-school of MÄ«mÄṃsÄ, means non-perception, negative/cognitive proof.[35] Anupalabdhi pramana suggests that knowing a negative, such as "there is no jug in this room" is a form of valid knowledge. If something can be observed or inferred or proven as non-existent or impossible, then one knows more than what one did without such means.[36] In the two schools of Hinduism that consider Anupalabdhi as epistemically valuable, a valid conclusion is either sadrupa (positive) or asadrupa (negative) relation - both correct and valuable. Like other pramana, Indian scholars refined Anupalabdi to four types: non-perception of the cause, non-perception of the effect, non-perception of object, and non-perception of contradiction. Only two schools of Hinduism accepted and developed the concept "non-perception" as a pramana. The schools that endorsed Anupalabdi affirmed that it as valid and useful when the other five pramanas fail in one's pursuit of knowledge and truth.[37]
Abhava (अà¤à¤¾à¤µ) means non-existence. Some scholars consider Anupalabdi to be same as Abhava,[5] while others consider Anupalabdi and Abhava as different.[37][38] Abhava-pramana has been discussed in ancient Hindu texts in the context of Padartha (पदारà¥à¤¥, referent of a term). A Padartha is defined as that which is simultaneously Astitva (existent), Jneyatva (knowable) and Abhidheyatva (nameable).[39] Specific examples of padartha, states Bartley, include dravya (substance), guna (quality), karma (activity/motion), samanya/jati (universal/class property), samavaya (inherence) and vishesha (individuality). Abhava is then explained as "referents of negative expression" in contrast to "referents of positive expression" in Padartha.[39] An absence, state the ancient scholars, is also "existent, knowable and nameable", giving the example of negative numbers, silence as a form of testimony, asatkaryavada theory of causation, and analysis of deficit as real and valuable. Abhava was further refined in four types, by the schools of Hinduism that accepted it as a useful method of epistemology: dhvamsa (termination of what existed), atyanta-abhava (impossibility, absolute non-existence, contradiction), anyonya-abhava (mutual negation, reciprocal absence) and pragavasa (prior, antecedent non-existence).[39][40]
Sabda
Åšabda (शबà¥à¤¦) means relying on word, testimony of past or present reliable experts.[5][35] Hiriyanna explains Sabda-pramana as a concept which means reliable expert testimony. The schools of Hinduism which consider it epistemically valid suggest that a human being needs to know numerous facts, and with the limited time and energy available, he can learn only a fraction of those facts and truths directly.[41] He must rely on others, his parent, family, friends, teachers, ancestors and kindred members of society to rapidly acquire and share knowledge and thereby enrich each other's lives. This means of gaining proper knowledge is either spoken or written, but through Sabda (words).[41] The reliability of the source is important, and legitimate knowledge can only come from the Sabda of reliable sources.[35][41] The disagreement between the schools of Hinduism has been on how to establish reliability. Some schools, such as Carvaka, state that this is never possible, and therefore Sabda is not a proper pramana. Other schools debate means to establish reliability.[42]
Relation to Vedanta school
An interesting feature of the MimÄṃsÄ school of philosophy is its unique epistemological theory of the intrinsic validity of all cognition as such. It is held that all knowledge is ipso facto true (Skt. svataḥprÄmÄṇyavÄda). Thus, what is to be proven is not the truth of a cognition, but its falsity. The MimÄṃsÄkas advocate the self-validity of knowledge both in respect of its origin (utpatti) and ascertainment (jñapti). Not only did the MimÄṃsÄkas make the very great use of this theory to establish the unchallengeable validity of the Vedas, but later Vedantists also drew freely upon this particular MimÄṃsÄ contribution.
Metaphysics and beliefs
The core tenets of PÅ«rva MÄ«mÄṃsÄ are ritualism (orthopraxy), anti-asceticism and anti-mysticism. The central aim of the school is elucidation of the nature of dharma, understood as a set ritual obligations and prerogatives to be performed properly.
Atheism
MÄ«mÄṃsÄ theorists decided that the evidence allegedly proving the existence of God was insufficient. They argue that there was no need to postulate a maker for the world, just as there was no need for an author to compose the Vedas or a God to validate the rituals.[43] MÄ«mÄṃsÄ argues that the Gods named in the Vedas have no existence apart from the mantras that speak their names. To that regard, the power of the mantras is what is seen as the power of Gods.[44]
Dharma
Dharma as understood by PÅ«rva MÄ«mÄṃsÄ can be loosely translated into English as "virtue", "morality" or "duty". The PÅ«rva MÄ«mÄṃsÄ school traces the source of the knowledge of dharma neither to sense-experience nor inference, but to verbal cognition (i.e. knowledge of words and meanings) according to Vedas. In this respect it is related to the NyÄya school, the latter, however, accepts only four sources of knowledge (pramÄṇa) as valid.[45]
The PÅ«rva MÄ«mÄṃsÄ school held dharma to be equivalent to following the prescriptions of the SaṃhitÄs and their BrÄhmaṇa commentaries relating the correct performance of Vedic rituals. Seen in this light, PÅ«rva MÄ«mÄṃsÄ is essentially ritualist (orthopraxy), placing great weight on the performance of karma or action as enjoined by the Vedas.
Relation to VedÄnta
Emphasis of Yajnic KarmakÄṇá¸as in PÅ«rva MÄ«mÄṃsÄ is erroneously interpreted by some to be an opposition to JñÄnakÄṇá¸a of VedÄnta and Upaniá¹£ads. PÅ«rva MÄ«mÄṃsÄ does not discuss topics related to JñÄnakÄṇá¸a, such as salvation (moká¹£a), but it never speaks against moká¹£a. VedÄnta quotes Jaimini's belief in Brahman as well as in moká¹£a:
In Uttara-MÄ«mÄṃsÄ or VedÄnta (4.4.5-7), BÄá¸arÄyaṇa cites Jaimini as saying (बà¥à¤°à¤¾à¤¹à¥à¤®à¥‡à¤£ जैमिनिरूपनà¥à¤¯à¤¾à¤¸à¤¾à¤¦à¤¿à¤à¥à¤¯à¤ƒ) "(The mukta Puruá¹£a is united with the Brahman) as if it were like the Brahman, because descriptions (in Åšruti etc) prove so".
In VedÄnta (1.2.28), BÄá¸arÄyaṇa cites Jaimini as saying that "There is no contradiction in taking VaishvÄnara as the supreme Brahman".
In 1.2.31, Jaimini is again quoted by BÄá¸arÄyana as saying that the nirguna (attribute-less) Brahman can manifest itself as having a form.
In 4.3.12, BÄdarÄyana again cites Jaimini as saying that the mukta Purusha attains Brahman.
In PÅ«rva MÄ«mÄṃsÄ too, Jaimini emphasises the importance of faith in and attachment to the Omnipotent Supreme Being Whom Jaimini calls "The Omnipotent Pradhaana" (The Main):
PÅ«rva MÄ«mÄṃsÄ 6.3.1: "sarvaÅ›aktau pravá¹›ttiḥ syÄt tathÄbhÅ«topadeÅ›Ät" (सरà¥à¤µà¤¶à¤•à¥à¤¤à¥Œ पà¥à¤°à¤µà¥ƒà¤¤à¥à¤¤à¤¿à¤ƒ सà¥à¤¯à¤¾à¤¤à¥ तथाà¤à¥‚तोपदेशातà¥). The term upadeÅ›a here means instructions of the Å›Ästras as taught. We should tend towards the omnipotent supreme being. In the context of PÅ«rva MÄ«mÄṃsÄ 6.3.1 shown above, next two sutras becomes significant, in which this Omnipotent Being is termed as "pradhÄna", and keeping away from Him is said to be a "doá¹£a", hence all beings are asked to get related ("abhisambandhÄt" in tadakarmaṇi ca doá¹£as tasmÄt tato viÅ›eá¹£aḥ syÄt pradhÄnenÄbhisambandhÄt; Jaimini 6, 3.3) to the "Omnipotent Main Being" (api vÄpy ekadeÅ›e syÄt pradhÄne hy arthanirvá¹›ttir guṇamÄtram itarat tadarthatvÄt; Jaimini 6, 3.2). Karma-MÄ«mÄṃsÄ supports the Vedas, and Rgveda says that one Truth is variously named by the sages. It is irrelevant whether we call Him as PradhÄna or Brahman or VaishvÄnara or Shiva or God.
History
The school's origins lie in the scholarly traditions of the final centuries BCE, when the priestly ritualism of Vedic sacrifice was being marginalized by Buddhism and Vedanta. To counteract this challenge, several groups emerged dedicated to demonstrating the validity of the Vedic texts by rigid formulation of rules for their interpretation. The school gathers momentum in the Gupta period with ÅšÄbara, and reaches its apex in the 7th to 8th centuries with KumÄrila Bhaá¹á¹a and PrabhÄkara.
The school for some time in the Early Middle Ages exerted near-dominant influence on learned Hindu thought, and is credited as a major force contributing to the decline of Buddhism in India, but it has fallen into decline in the High Middle Ages and today is all but eclipsed by Vedanta.[46]
Mimamsa texts
The foundational text for the MÄ«mÄṃsÄ school is the Purva MÄ«mÄṃsÄ Sutras of Jaimini (ca. 3rd to 1st century BCE). A major commentary was composed by ÅšÄbara in ca. the 5th or 6th century CE. The school reaches its height with KumÄrila Bhaá¹á¹a and PrabhÄkara (fl. ca. 700 CE). Both Kumarila Bhatta and PrabhÄkara (along with MurÄri, whose work is no more extant) have written extensive commentaries on ÅšÄbara's MÄ«mÄṃsÄsÅ«trabhÄá¹£yam. KumÄrila Bhaá¹á¹a, Mandana MiÅ›ra, PÄrthasÄrathi MiÅ›ra, Sucarita MiÅ›ra, Ramakrishna Bhatta, Madhava Subhodini, Sankara Bhatta, Krsnayajvan, Anantadeva, Gaga Bhatta, Ragavendra Tirtha, VijayIndhra Tirtha, Appayya Dikshitar, Paruthiyur Krishna Sastri, Mahomahapadyaya Sri Ramsubba Sastri, Sri Venkatsubba Sastri, Sri A. Chinnaswami Sastri, Sengalipuram Vaidhyanatha Dikshitar were some of the Mimamsa Scholars.
The MÄ«mÄá¹sÄ SÅ«tra of Jaimini (c. 3rd century BCE) has summed up the general rules of nyÄya for Vedic interpretation. The text has 12 chapters, of which the first chapter is of philosophical value. The commentaries on the MÄ«mÄá¹sÄ SÅ«tra by Bhartá¹›mitra, BhavadÄsa, Hari and Upavará¹£a are no more extant. Åšabara (c. 1st century BCE) is the first commentator of the MÄ«mÄá¹sÄ SÅ«tra, whose work is available to us. His bhÄá¹£ya is the basis of all later works of MÄ«mÄá¹sÄ . KumÄrila Bhaá¹á¹a (7th century CE), the founder of the first school of the MÄ«mÄá¹sÄ commented on both the SÅ«tra and its Åšabara BhÄá¹£ya. His treatise consists of 3 parts, the ÅšlokavÄrttika, the TantravÄrttika and the Ṭupá¹Ä«kÄ. Maná¸ana MiÅ›ra (8th century CE) was a follower of KumÄrila, who wrote Vidhiviveka and MÄ«mÄá¹sÄnukramaṇī. There are several commentaries on the works of KumÄrila. Sucarita MiÅ›ra wrote a KÄÅ›ikÄ (commentary) on the ÅšlokavÄrttika. SomeÅ›vara Bhatta wrote NyÄyasudhÄ, also known as RÄṇaka, a commentary on the TantravÄrttika. PÄrthasarathi MiÅ›ra wrote NyÄyaratnÄkara (1300 CE), another commentary on the ÅšlokavÄrttika. He also wrote ÅšÄstradÄ«pikÄ, an independent work on the MÄ«mÄá¹sÄ and Tantraratna. Venkaá¹a DÄ«ká¹£ita’s VÄrttikabharaṇya is a commentary on the Ṭupá¹Ä«kÄ. PrabhÄkara (8th century CE), the originator of the second school of the MÄ«mÄá¹sÄ wrote his commentary Bá¹›hatÄ« on the Åšabara BhÄá¹£ya. ÅšÄlikanÄtha’s ṚjuvimalÄ (9th century CE) is a commentary on the Bá¹›hatÄ«. His PrakaraṇapañcikÄ is an independent work of this school and the PariÅ›iá¹£á¹a is a brief explanation of the Åšabara BhÄá¹£ya. BhavanÄtha’s NyÄyaviveka deals with the views of this school in details. The founder of the third school of the MÄ«mÄá¹sÄ was MurÄri, whose works have not reached us.
Ä€padeva (17th century) wrote an elementary work on the MÄ«mÄá¹sÄ, known as MÄ«mÄá¹sÄnyÄyaprakaÅ›a or Ä€padevÄ«. Arthasaá¹graha of LaugÄká¹£i BhÄskara is based on the Ä€padevÄ«. VedÄnta DeÅ›ika’s ÅšeÅ›vara MÄ«mÄá¹sÄ was an attempt to combine the views of the MÄ«mÄá¹sÄ and the VedÄnta schools.[47]
See also
Notes
- ↑ Mimamsa Meriam-Webster Dictionary (2011)
- ↑ Mimamsa Encyclopedia Britannica (2014)
- 1 2 3 4 Oliver Leaman (2006), Shruti, in Encyclopaedia of Asian Philosophy, Routledge, ISBN 978-0415862530, page 503
- 1 2 3 4 5 6 Chris Bartley (2013), Purva Mimamsa, in Encyclopaedia of Asian Philosophy (Editor: Oliver Leaman), Routledge, 978-0415862530, page 443-445
- 1 2 3 4 5 6 DPS Bhawuk (2011), Spirituality and Indian Psychology (Editor: Anthony Marsella), Springer, ISBN 978-1-4419-8109-7, page 172
- 1 2 3 Gavin Flood, An Introduction to Hinduism, Cambridge University Press, ISBN 978-0521438780, page 225
- ↑ John A. Grimes, A Concise Dictionary of Indian Philosophy: Sanskrit Terms Defined in English, State University of New York Press, ISBN 978-0791430675, page 238
- ↑ Neville, Robert (2001). Religious truth. SUNY Press.
- ↑ Worthington, Vivian (1982). A history of yoga. Routledge. p. 66.
- ↑ Peter M. Scharf, The Denotation of Generic Terms in Ancient Indian Philosophy (1996), Chapter 3
- ↑ Annette Wilke and Oliver Moebus (2011), Sound and Communication: An Aesthetic Cultural History of Sanskrit Hinduism, Walter de Gruyter GmbH (Berlin), ISBN 978-3110181593, pages 23-24, 551-663
- ↑ M. Hiriyanna (1993), Outlines of Indian Philosophy, Motilal Banarsidass, ISBN 978-8120810860, page 323-325
- 1 2 M. Hiriyanna (1993), Outlines of Indian Philosophy, Motilal Banarsidass, ISBN 978-8120810860, page 298-335
- 1 2 Mimamsa, Monier Williams Sanskrit-English Dictionary, Cologne Digital Sanskrit Lexicon (Germany)
- ↑ M. Hiriyanna (1993), Outlines of Indian Philosophy, Motilal Banarsidass, ISBN 978-8120810860, page 299
- 1 2 Donald R. Davis, Jr (2010). The Spirit of Hindu Law. Cambridge University Press. pp. 47–48. ISBN 978-1-139-48531-9.
- 1 2 Francis Xavier Clooney (1990). Thinking Ritually: Rediscovering the PÅ«rva MÄ«mÄṃsÄ of Jaimini. De Nobili, Vienna. pp. 25–28. ISBN 978-3-900271-21-3.
- 1 2 MM Kamal (1998), The Epistemology of the Carvaka Philosophy, Journal of Indian and Buddhist Studies, 46(2): 13-16
- ↑ B Matilal (1992), Perception: An Essay in Indian Theories of Knowledge, Oxford University Press, ISBN 978-0198239765
- 1 2 Karl Potter (1977), Meaning and Truth, in Encyclopedia of Indian Philosophies, Volume 2, Princeton University Press, Reprinted in 1995 by Motilal Banarsidass, ISBN 81-208-0309-4, pages 160-168
- ↑ Karl Potter (1977), Meaning and Truth, in Encyclopedia of Indian Philosophies, Volume 2, Princeton University Press, Reprinted in 1995 by Motilal Banarsidass, ISBN 81-208-0309-4, pages 168-169
- ↑ Karl Potter (1977), Meaning and Truth, in Encyclopedia of Indian Philosophies, Volume 2, Princeton University Press, Reprinted in 1995 by Motilal Banarsidass, ISBN 81-208-0309-4, pages 170-172
- ↑ W Halbfass (1991), Tradition and Reflection, State University of New York Press, ISBN 0-7914-0362-9, page 26-27
- ↑ Carvaka school is the exception
- 1 2 James Lochtefeld, "Anumana" in The Illustrated Encyclopedia of Hinduism, Vol. 1: A-M, Rosen Publishing. ISBN 0-8239-2287-1, page 46-47
- ↑ Karl Potter (2002), Presuppositions of India's Philosophies, Motilal Banarsidass, ISBN 81-208-0779-0
- ↑ Monier Williams (1893), Indian Wisdom - Religious, Philosophical and Ethical Doctrines of the Hindus, Luzac & Co, London, page 61
- ↑ VN Jha (1986), "The upamana-pramana in Purvamimamsa", SILLE, pages 77-91
- 1 2 James Lochtefeld, "Upamana" in The Illustrated Encyclopedia of Hinduism, Vol. 2: N-Z, Rosen Publishing. ISBN 0-8239-2287-1, page 721
- 1 2 Monier Williams (1893), Indian Wisdom - Religious, Philosophical and Ethical Doctrines of the Hindus, Luzac & Co, London, pages 457-458
- ↑ Arthapatti Encyclopedia Britannica (2012)
- ↑ James Lochtefeld, "Arthapatti" in The Illustrated Encyclopedia of Hinduism, Vol. 1: A-M, Rosen Publishing. ISBN 0-8239-2287-1, page 55
- ↑ Stephen Phillips (1996), Classical Indian Metaphysics, Motilal Banarsidass, ISBN 978-8120814899, pages 41-63
- ↑ DM Datta (1932), The Six Ways of Knowing: A Critical study of the Advaita theory of knowledge, University of Calcutta, Reprinted in 1992 as ISBN 978-8120835269, pages 221-253
- 1 2 3
- Eliott Deutsche (2000), in Philosophy of Religion : Indian Philosophy Vol 4 (Editor: Roy Perrett), Routledge, ISBN 978-0815336112, pages 245-248;
- John A. Grimes, A Concise Dictionary of Indian Philosophy: Sanskrit Terms Defined in English, State University of New York Press, ISBN 978-0791430675, page 238
- ↑ James Lochtefeld, "Abhava" in The Illustrated Encyclopedia of Hinduism, Vol. 1: A-M, Rosen Publishing. ISBN 0-8239-2287-1, page 1
- 1 2 D Sharma (1966), Epistemological negative dialectics of Indian logic — AbhÄva versus Anupalabdhi, Indo-Iranian Journal, 9(4): 291-300
- ↑ Karl Potter (1977), Meaning and Truth, in Encyclopedia of Indian Philosophies, Volume 2, Princeton University Press, Reprinted in 1995 by Motilal Banarsidass, ISBN 81-208-0309-4, pages 155-174, 227-255
- 1 2 3 Chris Bartley (2013), Padartha, in Encyclopaedia of Asian Philosophy (Editor: Oliver Leaman), Routledge, ISBN 978-0415862530, pages 415-416
- ↑ Mohan Lal (Editor), The Encyclopaedia of Indian Literature, Vol. 5, Sahitya Akademy, ISBN 81-260-1221-8, page 3958
- 1 2 3 M. Hiriyanna (2000), The Essentials of Indian Philosophy, Motilal Banarsidass, ISBN 978-8120813304, page 43
- ↑ P. Billimoria (1988), ÅšabdapramÄṇa: Word and Knowledge, Studies of Classical India Volume 10, Springer, ISBN 978-94-010-7810-8, pages 1-30
- ↑ Neville, Robert. Religious truth. p. 51.
- ↑ Coward, Harold. The perfectibility of human nature in eastern and western thought. p. 114.
- ↑ Kapoor, Subodh (2004). The Philosophy Of Vaisnavism. Cosmo Publications. p. 60. ISBN 978-81-7755-886-9.
- ↑ Göhler (1995), p. 5f.
- ↑ Radhakrishnan, S. Indian Philosophy, Vol. II, Oxford University Press, New Delhi, 2006, ISBN 0-19-563820-4, pp.376-78
References
- Lars Göhler, Wort und Text bei KumÄrila Bhaá¹á¹a: Studie zur mittelalterlichen indischen Sprachphilophie und Hermeneutik, Europäische Hochschulschriften. Reihe 20, Philosophie ; vol. 468, Lang (1995), ISBN 3-631-48821-1.
Further reading
- Verpoorten, Jean-Marie (1987). Mimamsa literature (A History of Indian literature). Otto Harrassowitz Verlag. ISBN 978-3447026765.
- Mahesh Chandra Nyayratna Bhattacharyya, ed. (1889). The Mimansa Darsana (Bibliotheca Indica). Baptist Mission Press.
- Chatterjee, Satischandra; Datta, Dhirendramohan (1984). An Introduction to Indian Philosophy (Eighth Reprint ed.). Calcutta: University of Calcutta.
- Müeller, Max (1899). Six Systems of Indian Philosophy; Samkhya and Yoga, Naya and Vaiseshika. Calcutta: Susil Gupta (India) Ltd. ISBN 0-7661-4296-5. Reprint edition; Originally published under the title of The Six Systems of Indian Philosophy.
- Radhakrishnan, S.; Moore, CA (1967). A Sourcebook in Indian Philosophy. Princeton. ISBN 0-691-01958-4.
- R.A. Ramaswami Shastri, A Short History Of The Purva Mimamsa Shastra, Annamalai University Sanskrit Series No. 3 (1936).
- Zimmer, Heinrich (1951). Philosophies of India. New York, New York: Princeton University Press. ISBN 0-691-01758-1. Bollingen Series XXVI; Edited by Joseph Campbell.
External links
- Purva Mimamsa Sutras of Jaimini
- Introduction to Purva-Mimamsa G. Jha (Translator), Asiatic Society of Bengal
- Complete Lectures on Purva Mimamsa Sutras of Jaimini at ShastraNethralaya
- S. Srikanta Sastri, "The Logical system of Madvacharya" Published in Poona Oriental Series, No. 75 - "A Volume of Studies in Indology", presented to Prof P. V. Kane on his 60th birthday
|
|