Sahlqvist formula

In modal logic, Sahlqvist formulas are a certain kind of modal formula with remarkable properties. The Sahlqvist correspondence theorem states that every Sahlqvist formula is canonical, and corresponds to a first-order definable class of Kripke frames.

Sahlqvist's definition characterizes a decidable set of modal formulas with first-order correspondents. Since it is undecidable, by Chagrova's theorem, whether an arbitrary modal formula has a first-order correspondent, there are formulas with first-order frame conditions that are not Sahlqvist [Chagrova 1991] (see the examples below). Hence Sahlqvist formulas define only a (decidable) subset of modal formulas with first-order correspondents.

Definition

Sahlqvist formulas are built up from implications, where the consequent is positive and the antecedent is of a restricted form.

Examples of Sahlqvist formulas

p \rightarrow \Diamond p
Its first-order corresponding formula is \forall x \; Rxx, and it defines all reflexive frames
p \rightarrow \Box\Diamond p
Its first-order corresponding formula is \forall x \forall y [Rxy \rightarrow Ryx], and it defines all symmetric frames
\Diamond \Diamond p \rightarrow \Diamond p or \Box p \rightarrow \Box \Box p
Its first-order corresponding formula is \forall x \forall y \forall z [(Rxy \land Ryz) \rightarrow Rxz], and it defines all transitive frames
\Diamond p \rightarrow \Diamond \Diamond p or \Box \Box p \rightarrow \Box p
Its first-order corresponding formula is \forall x \forall y [Rxy \rightarrow \exists z (Rxz \land Rzy)], and it defines all dense frames
\Box p \rightarrow \Diamond p
Its first-order corresponding formula is \forall x \exists y \; Rxy, and it defines all right-unbounded frames (also called serial)
\Diamond\Box p \rightarrow \Box\Diamond p
Its first-order corresponding formula is \forall x \forall x_1 \forall z_0 [Rxx_1 \land Rxz_0 \rightarrow \exists z_1 (Rx_1z_1 \land Rz_0z_1)], and it is the Church-Rosser property.

Examples of non-Sahlqvist formulas

\Box\Diamond p \rightarrow \Diamond \Box p
This is the McKinsey formula; it does not have a first-order frame condition.
\Box(\Box p \rightarrow p) \rightarrow \Box p
The Löb axiom is not Sahlqvist; again, it does not have a first-order frame condition.
(\Box\Diamond p \rightarrow \Diamond \Box p) \land (\Diamond\Diamond q \rightarrow \Diamond q)
The conjunction of the McKinsey formula and the (4) axiom has a first-order frame condition (the conjunction of the transitivity property with the property  \forall x[\forall y(Rxy \rightarrow \exists z[Ryz]) \rightarrow \exists y(Rxy \wedge \forall z[Ryz \rightarrow z = y])] ) but is not equivalent to any Sahlqvist formula.

Kracht's theorem

When a Sahlqvist formula is used as an axiom in a normal modal logic, the logic is guaranteed to be complete with respect to the elementary class of frames the axiom defines. This result comes from the Sahlqvist completeness theorem [Modal Logic, Blackburn et al., Theorem 4.42]. But there is also a converse theorem, namely a theorem that states which first-order conditions are the correspondents of Sahlqvist formulas. Kracht's theorem states that any Sahlqvist formula locally corresponds to a Kracht formula; and conversely, every Kracht formula is a local first-order correspondent of some Sahlqvist formula which can be effectively obtained from the Kracht formula [Modal Logic, Blackburn et al., Theorem 3.59].

References

This article is issued from Wikipedia - version of the Tuesday, April 21, 2015. The text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution/Share Alike but additional terms may apply for the media files.