Skolem normal form
In mathematical logic, reduction to Skolem normal form (SNF) is a method for removing existential quantifiers from formal logic statements, often performed as the first step in an automated theorem prover.
A formula of first-order logic is in Skolem normal form (named after Thoralf Skolem) if it is in prenex normal form with only universal first-order quantifiers. Every first-order formula may be converted into Skolem normal form while not changing its satisfiability via a process called Skolemization (sometimes spelled "Skolemnization"). The resulting formula is not necessarily equivalent to the original one, but is equisatisfiable with it: it is satisfiable if and only if the original one is satisfiable.[1]
The simplest form of Skolemization is for existentially quantified variables which are not inside the scope of a universal quantifier. These may be replaced simply by creating new constants. For example, may be changed to
, where
is a new constant (does not occur anywhere else in the formula).
More generally, Skolemization is performed by replacing every existentially quantified variable with a term
whose function symbol
is new. The variables of this term are as follows. If the formula is in prenex normal form,
are the variables that are universally quantified and whose quantifiers precede that of
. In general, they are the variables that are quantified universally and such that
occurs in the scope of their quantifiers. The function
introduced in this process is called a Skolem function (or Skolem constant if it is of zero arity) and the term is called a Skolem term.
As an example, the formula is not in Skolem normal form because it contains the existential quantifier
. Skolemization replaces
with
, where
is a new function symbol, and removes the quantification over
. The resulting formula is
. The Skolem term
contains
, but not
, because the quantifier to be removed
is in the scope of
, but not in that of
; since this formula is in prenex normal form, this is equivalent to saying that, in the list of quantifiers,
precedes
while
does not. The formula obtained by this transformation is satisfiable if and only if the original formula is.
How Skolemization works
Skolemization works by applying a second-order equivalence in conjunction to the definition of first-order satisfiability. The equivalence provides a way for "moving" an existential quantifier before a universal one.
where
is a function that maps
to
.
Intuitively, the sentence "for every there exists a
such that
" is converted into the equivalent form "there exists a function
mapping every
into a
such that, for every
it holds
".
This equivalence is useful because the definition of first-order satisfiability implicitly existentially quantifies over the evaluation of function symbols. In particular, a first-order formula is satisfiable if there exists a model
and an evaluation
of the free variables of the formula that evaluate the formula to true. The model contains the evaluation of all function symbols; therefore, Skolem functions are implicitly, existentially quantified. In the example above,
is satisfiable if and only if there exists a model
, which contains an evaluation for
, such that
is true for some evaluation of its free variables (none in this case). This may be expressed in second order as
. By the above equivalence, this is the same as the satisfiability of
.
At the meta-level, first-order satisfiability of a formula may be written with a little abuse of notation as
, where
is a model,
is an evaluation of the free variables, and
means that
is true in
under
. Since first-order models contain the evaluation of all function symbols, any Skolem function
contains is implicitly, existentially quantified by
. As a result, after replacing an existential quantifier over variables into an existential quantifiers over functions at the front of the formula, the formula still may be treated as a first-order one by removing these existential quantifiers. This final step of treating
as
may be completed because functions are implicitly existentially quantified by
in the definition of first-order satisfiability.
Correctness of Skolemization may be shown on the example formula as follows. This formula is satisfied by a model
if and only if, for each possible value for
in the domain of the model, there exists a value for
in the domain of the model that makes
true. By the axiom of choice, there exists a function
such that
. As a result, the formula
is satisfiable, because it has the model obtained by adding the evaluation of
to
. This shows that
is satisfiable only if
is satisfiable as well. In the other way around, if
is satisfiable, then there exists a model
that satisfies it; this model includes an evaluation for the function
such that, for every value of
, the formula
holds. As a result,
is satisfied by the same model because one may choose, for every value of
, the value
, where
is evaluated according to
.
Uses of Skolemization
One of the uses of Skolemization is automated theorem proving. For example, in the method of analytic tableaux, whenever a formula whose leading quantifier is existential occurs, the formula obtained by removing that quantifier via Skolemization may be generated. For example, if occurs in a tableau, where
are the free variables of
, then
may be added to the same branch of the tableau. This addition does not alter the satisfiability of the tableau: every model of the old formula may be extended, by adding a suitable evaluation of
, to a model of the new formula.
This form of Skolemization is an improvement over "classical" Skolemization in that, only variables that are free in the formula are placed in the Skolem term. This is an improvement because the semantics of tableau may implicitly place the formula in the scope of some universally quantified variables that are not in the formula itself; these variables are not in the Skolem term, while they would be there according to the original definition of Skolemization. Another improvement that may be used is applying the same Skolem function symbol for formulae that are identical up to variable renaming.[2]
Another use is in the resolution method for first order logic, where formulas are represented as sets of clauses understood to be universally quantified. (For an example see drinker paradox.)
Skolem theories
In general, if is a theory and for each formula
with free variables
there is a Skolem function, then
is called a Skolem theory.[3] For example, by the above, arithmetic with the Axiom of Choice is a Skolem theory.
Every Skolem theory is model complete, i.e. every substructure of a model is an elementary substructure. Given a model M of a Skolem theory T, the smallest substructure containing a certain set A is called the Skolem hull of A. The Skolem hull of A is an atomic prime model over A.
See also
- Herbrandization, the dual of Skolemization
- Predicate functor logic
Notes
- ↑ "Normal Forms and Skolemization" (PDF). max planck institut informatik. Retrieved 15 December 2012.
- ↑ R. Hähnle. Tableaux and related methods. Handbook of Automated Reasoning.
- ↑
References
- Hodges, Wilfrid (1997), A shorter model theory, Cambridge University Press, ISBN 978-0-521-58713-6
External links
- Hazewinkel, Michiel, ed. (2001), "Skolem function", Encyclopedia of Mathematics, Springer, ISBN 978-1-55608-010-4
- Skolemization on PlanetMath.org
- Skolemization by Hector Zenil, The Wolfram Demonstrations Project.
- Weisstein, Eric W., "SkolemizedForm", MathWorld.