Quantum mind
The quantum mind or quantum consciousness[1] group of hypotheses propose that classical mechanics cannot explain consciousness. It posits that quantum mechanical phenomena, such as quantum entanglement and superposition, may play an important part in the brain's function and could form the basis of an explanation of consciousness. Tarlaci & Pregnolato (2015)[2] highlight the following distinct issues in quantum mind studies:
- The relationship of consciousness to the superposition-destroying observer in quantum mechanics
- Whether quantum physics has significance in biology
- Whether quantum physics has significance for the nervous system
- Whether psychiatric disorders can be explained by quantum physical changes
History
Eugene Wigner developed the idea that quantum mechanics has something to do with the workings of the mind . He proposed that the wave function collapses due to its interaction with consciousness. Freeman Dyson argued that "mind, as manifested by the capacity to make choices, is to some extent inherent in every electron."[3]
Other contemporary physicists and philosophers considered these arguments to be unconvincing.[4] Victor Stenger characterized quantum consciousness as a "myth" having "no scientific basis" that "should take its place along with gods, unicorns and dragons."[5]
David Chalmers argued against quantum consciousness. He instead discussed how quantum mechanics may relate to dualistic consciousness.[6] Chalmers is skeptical of the ability of any new physics to resolve the hard problem of consciousness.[7][8]
Quantum mind approaches
Bohm
David Bohm viewed quantum theory and relativity as contradictory, which implied a more fundamental level in the universe.[9] He claimed both quantum theory and relativity pointed towards this deeper theory, which he formulated as a quantum field theory. This more fundamental level was proposed to represent an undivided wholeness and an implicate order, from which arises the explicate order of the universe as we experience it.
Bohm's proposed implicate order applies both to matter and consciousness. He suggested that it could explain the relationship between them. He saw mind and matter as projections into our explicate order from the underlying implicate order. Bohm claimed that when we look at matter, we see nothing that helps us to understand consciousness.
Bohm discussed the experience of listening to music. He believed the feeling of movement and change that make up our experience of music derive from holding the immediate past and the present in the brain together. The musical notes from the past are transformations rather than memories. The notes that were implicate in the immediate past become explicate in the present. Bohm viewed this as consciousness emerging from the implicate order.
Bohm saw the movement, change or flow, and the coherence of experiences, such as listening to music, as a manifestation of the implicate order. He claimed to derive evidence for this from Jean Piaget's[10] work on infants. He held these studies to show that young children learn about time and space because they have a "hard-wired" understanding of movement as part of the implicate order. He compared this "hard-wiring" to Chomsky's theory that grammar is "hard-wired" into human brains.
Bohm never proposed a specific means by which his proposal could be falsified, nor a neural mechanism through which his "implicate order" could emerge in a way relevant to consciousness.[9] Bohm later collaborated on Karl Pribram's holonomic brain theory as a model of quantum consciousness.[11]
According to philosopher Paavo Pylkkänen, Bohm's suggestion "leads naturally to the assumption that the physical correlate of the logical thinking process is at the classically describable level of the brain, while the basic thinking process is at the quantum-theoretically describable level."[12]
Penrose and Hameroff
Theoretical physicist Roger Penrose and anaesthesiologist Stuart Hameroff collaborated to produce the theory known as Orchestrated Objective Reduction (Orch-OR). Penrose and Hameroff initially developed their ideas separately and later collaborated to produce Orch-OR in the early 1990s. The theory was reviewed and updated by the authors in late 2013.[13][14]
Penrose's argument stemmed from Gödel's incompleteness theorems. In Penrose's first book on consciousness, The Emperor's New Mind (1989), he argued that while a formal system cannot prove its own inconsistency, Gödel’s unprovable results are provable by human mathematicians.[15] He took this disparity to mean that human mathematicians are not formal proof systems and are not running a computable algorithm. According to Bringsjorg and Xiao, this line of reasoning is based on fallacious equivocation on the meaning of computation.[16]
Penrose determined wave function collapse was the only possible physical basis for a non-computable process. Dissatisfied with its randomness, Penrose proposed a new form of wave function collapse that occurred in isolation and called it objective reduction. He suggested each quantum superposition has its own piece of spacetime curvature and that when these become separated by more than one Planck length they become unstable and collapse.[17] Penrose suggested that objective reduction represented neither randomness nor algorithmic processing but instead a non-computable influence in spacetime geometry from which mathematical understanding and, by later extension, consciousness derived.[17]
Hameroff provided a hypothesis that microtubules would be suitable hosts for quantum behavior.[18] Microtubules are composed of tubulin protein dimer subunits. The dimers each have hydrophobic pockets that are 8 nm apart and that may contain delocalized pi electrons. Tubulins have other smaller non-polar regions that contain pi electron-rich indole rings separated by only about 2 nm. Hameroff proposed that these electrons are close enough to become entangled.[19] Hameroff originally suggested the tubulin-subunit electrons would form a Bose–Einstein condensate, but this was discredited.[20] He then proposed a Frohlich condensate, a hypothetical coherent oscillation of dipolar molecules. However, this too was experimentally discredited.[21]
Furthermore, he proposed that condensates in one neuron could extend to many others via gap junctions between neurons, forming a macroscopic quantum feature across an extended area of the brain. When the wave function of this extended condensate collapsed, it was suggested to non-computationally access mathematical understanding and ultimately conscious experience that were hypothetically embedded in the geometry of spacetime.
However, Orch-OR made numerous false biological predictions, and is not an accepted model of brain physiology.[22] The proposed predominance of 'A' lattice microtubules, more suitable for information processing, was falsified by Kikkawa et al.,[23][24] who showed all in vivo microtubules have a 'B' lattice and a seam. The proposed existence of gap junctions between neurons and glial cells was also falsified.[25] Orch-OR predicted that microtubule coherence reaches the synapses via dendritic lamellar bodies (DLBs), however De Zeeuw et al. proved this impossible,[26] by showing that DLBs are located micrometers away from gap junctions.[27]
In January 2014, Hameroff and Penrose claimed that the discovery of quantum vibrations in microtubules by Anirban Bandyopadhyay of the National Institute for Materials Science in Japan in March 2013[28] corroborates the Orch-OR theory.[14][29]
In early 2015 it was revealed that pulsed transcranial ultrasound seems to improve memory functioning in Alzheimer's mice as well as helping to break down amyloid plaques.[30] This could be relevant to Orch-OR. Ultrasound activated latent brain repair and cleanup mechanisms; if it was also helping to boost the disease-weakened cemi field within the neurons in a similar way to adding noise to a signal sometimes boosts it above the noise floor then a similar high frequency ultrasound transmitter tuned to the specific microtubule vibrations could work even in patients in a persistent vegetative state.
Umezawa, Vitiello, Freeman
Hiroomi Umezawa and collaborators proposed a quantum field theory of memory storage. Giuseppe Vitiello and Walter Freeman proposed a dialog model of the mind. This dialog takes place between the classical and the quantum parts of the brain.[31][32] Their quantum field theory models of brain dynamics are fundamentally different from the Penrose-Hameroff theory.
Pribram, Bohm, Kak
Karl Pribram's holonomic brain theory (quantum holography) invoked quantum mechanics to explain higher order processing by the mind.[33][34] He argued that his holonomic model solved the binding problem.[35] Pribram collaborated with Bohm in his work on the quantum approaches to mind and he provided evidence on how much of the processing in the brain was done in wholes.[36] He proposed that ordered water at dendritic membrane surfaces might operate by structuring Bose-Einstein condensation supporting quantum dynamics.[37]
Although Subhash Kak's work is not directly related to that of Pribram, he likewise proposed that the physical substrate to neural networks has a quantum basis,[38][39] but asserted that the quantum mind has machine-like limitations.[40] He points to a role for quantum theory in the distinction between machine intelligence and biological intelligence, but that in itself cannot explain all aspects of consciousness.[41][42]
Stapp
Henry Stapp proposed that quantum waves are reduced only when they interact with consciousness. He argues from the Orthodox Quantum Mechanics of John von Neumann that the quantum state collapses when the observer selects one among the alternative quantum possibilities as a basis for future action. The collapse, therefore, takes place in the expectation that the observer associated with the state. Stapp's work drew criticism from scientists such as David Bourget and Danko Georgiev.[43] Georgiev[44][45] criticized Stapp's model in two respects:
- Stapp's mind does not have its own wavefunction or density matrix, but nevertheless can act upon the brain using projection operators. Such usage is not compatible with standard quantum mechanics because one can attach any number of ghostly minds to any point in space that act upon physical quantum systems with any projection operators. Therefore, Stapp's model negates "the prevailing principles of physics".[44]
- Stapp's claim that quantum Zeno effect is robust against environmental decoherence directly contradicts a basic theorem in quantum information theory that acting with projection operators upon the density matrix of a quantum system can only increase the system's Von Neumann entropy.[44][45]
Criticism
The main argument against the quantum mind proposition is that quantum states in the brain would decohere before they reached a spatial or temporal scale at which they could be useful for neural processing. This argument was elaborated by Tegmark. His calculations allowed him to conclude that quantum systems in the brain decohere at sub-picosecond timescales generally assumed to be too short to control brain function.[46][47] However, the extent to which we can predict where and when quantum behavior will end is still unclear. It has been established that photosynthesis depends on quantum processes in order to efficiently convert sunlight into chemical energy.[48] In 2015 researchers discovered an anomaly in the properties of ice at very cold temperatures near 20 K, which they explain by the quantum tunneling of multiple protons simultaneously.[49] Many other macroscopic quantum phenomena have been discovered, see Macroscopic quantum phenomena.
See also
- Bohm interpretation of quantum mechanics
- Electromagnetic theories of consciousness
- Evolutionary neuroscience
- Hameroff-Penrose Orchestrated Objective Reduction
- Hard problem of consciousness
- Holonomic brain theory
- Mechanism (philosophy)
- Quantum cognition
- Theory of mind
References
- ↑ "Quantum Approaches to Consciousness". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. May 19, 2011 [First published Tue Nov 30, 2004].
- ↑ Tarlacı, Sultan; Pregnolato, Massimo (2015). "Quantum neurophysics: From non-living matter to quantum neurobiology and psychopathology.". International journal of psychophysiology : official journal of the International Organization of Psychophysiology. doi:10.1016/j.ijpsycho.2015.02.016. PMID 25668717.
- ↑ Dyson, Freeman (2004). Infinite in All Directions: Gifford Lectures Given at Aberdeen, Scotland April--November 1985 (1st Perennial ed.). New York: Perennial. p. 297. ISBN 0060728892.
- ↑ Searle, John R. (1997). The Mystery of Consciousness (1. ed.). New York: New York Review of Books. pp. 53–88. ISBN 9780940322066.
- ↑ Stenger, Victor. The Myth of Quantum Consciousness (PDF). The Humanist. 53 No 3 (May–June 1992). pp. 13–15.
- ↑ Stephen P. Stich; Ted A. Warfield (15 April 2008). The Blackwell Guide to Philosophy of Mind. Blackwell Philosophy Guides (John Wiley & Sons). p. 126. ISBN 9780470998755.
- ↑ David J. Chalmers (1995). "Facing Up to the Problem of Consciousness". Journal of Consciousness Studies 2 (3): 200–219.
- ↑ Chalmers, David J. (1997). The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory (Paperback ed.). New York: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-511789-9.
- 1 2 Bohm, David (2002). Wholeness and the Implicate Order. (Online-Ausg. ed.). Hoboken: Routledge. ISBN 0203995155.
- ↑ Piaget, Jean (1997). Jean Piaget: selected works. (The Origin of Intelligence in the Child) (Repr. ed.). London: Routledge. ISBN 9780415168861.
- ↑ Wade, Jenny (1996). Changes of Mind: A Holonomic Theory of the Evolution of Consciousness. Albany: State Univ. of New York Press. ISBN 9780791428498.
- ↑ Paavo Pylkkänen. "Can quantum analogies help us to understand the process of thought?" (PDF). Mind & Matter 12 (1): 61–91. p. 75.
- ↑ unattributed (2014-01-16). "Discovery of Quantum Vibrations in...". sciencedaily.com. Retrieved 2014-01-16.
- 1 2 "Discovery of Quantum Vibrations in "Microtubules" Inside Brain Neurons Corroborates Controversial 20-Year-Old Theory of Consciousness". Elsevier. Retrieved 2014-08-04.
- ↑ Gödel, Kurt (1992). On Formally Undecidable Propositions of Principia Mathematica and Related Systems (Reprint. ed.). New York: Dover Publications. ISBN 0486669807.
- ↑ Bringsjord, S. and Xiao, H. 2000. A Refutation of Penrose's Gödelian Case Against Artificial Intelligence. Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence
- 1 2 Penrose, Roger (1999). The Emperor's New Mind: Concerning Computers, Minds, and the Laws of Physics ([New edition] ed.). Oxford: Oxford Univ. Press. ISBN 0192861980.
- ↑ Penrose, Roger (1995). Shadows of the Mind: A Search for the Missing Science of Consciousness (Repr. (with corrections). ed.). Oxford [u.a.]: Oxford Univ. Press. ISBN 0198539789.
- ↑ Hameroff, Stuart (2008). "That's life! The geometry of π electron resonance clouds". In Abbott, D; Davies, P; Pati, A. Quantum aspects of life (PDF). World Scientific. pp. 403–434. Retrieved Jan 21, 2010.
- ↑ Roger Penrose & Stuart Hameroff (2011). "Consciousness in the Universe: Neuroscience, Quantum Space-Time Geometry and Orch OR Theory". Journal of Cosmology 14.
- ↑ Reimers, Jeffrey R.; McKemmish, Laura K.; McKenzie, Ross H.; Mark, Alan E.; Hush, Noel S. (17 March 2009). "Weak, strong, and coherent regimes of Fröhlich condensation and their applications to terahertz medicine and quantum consciousness". PNAS 106 (11): 4219–4224. Bibcode:2009PNAS..106.4219R. doi:10.1073/pnas.0806273106. PMC 2657444. PMID 19251667. Retrieved 10 June 2013.
- ↑ Khoshbin-e-Khoshnazar M.R. (2007). "Achilles' Heels of the 'Orch OR' Model".NeuroQuantology 5(1):182-185. doi: 10.14704/nq.2007.5.1.123
- ↑ Kikkawa, M., Ishikawa, T., Nakata, T., Wakabayashi, T., Hirokawa, N. (1994). "Direct visualization of the microtubule lattice seam both in vitro and in vivo". Journal of Cell Biology 127 (6): 1965–1971. doi:10.1083/jcb.127.6.1965. PMC 2120284. PMID 7806574.
- ↑ Kikkawa, M., Metlagel, Z. (2006). "A molecular "zipper" for microtubules". Cell 127 (7): 1302–1304. doi:10.1016/j.cell.2006.12.009. PMID 17190594.
- ↑ F. J. Binmöller & C. M. Müller (1992). "Postnatal development of dye-coupling among astrocytes in rat visual cortex". Glia 6 (2): 127–137. doi:10.1002/glia.440060207. PMID 1328051.
- ↑ De Zeeuw, C.I., Hertzberg, E.L., Mugnaini, E. (1995). "The dendritic lamellar body: A new neuronal organelle putatively associated with dendrodentritic gap junctions". Journal of Neuroscience 15 (2): 1587–1604. PMID 7869120.
- ↑ "Consciousness, the brain, and spacetime geometry". 2013-08-12. Retrieved 2014-01-16.
- ↑ "Atomic water channel controlling remarka... [Biosens Bioelectron. 2013] - PubMed - NCBI". Ncbi.nlm.nih.gov. 2014-05-14. Retrieved 2014-07-30.
- ↑ Osborne, Hannah (2014-01-16). "Quantum Vibrations in Brain Opens 'Pandora's Box' of Theories of Consciousness - Yahoo News UK". Uk.news.yahoo.com. Retrieved 2014-08-04.
- ↑ "Ultrasound 'breakthrough' in treating Alzheimer's - in mice - Health News - NHS Choices". Nhs.uk. 2015-03-12. Retrieved 2015-03-31.
- ↑ G. Vitiello, My Double Unveiled. John Benjamins, 2001.
- ↑ Freeman, W. and G. Vitiello, Nonlinear brain dynamics as macroscopic manifestation of underlying many-body dynamics. Physics of Life Reviews, vol. 3, pp 93-118, 2006.
- ↑ Pribram, K. H. (1999). Quantum holography: Is it relevant to brain function? Information Sciences, 115(1–4), 97–102.
- ↑ Pribram, K.H. (2004). Consciousness Reassessed. Mind and Matter, 2, 7–35.
- ↑ Pribram, K. (1999) Status Report: Quantum Holography and the Braln. Acta Polyiechnica Scandinavica: Emergence Complexity, Hierarchy, Organization, Vol. 2, pp. 33-60.
- ↑ Pribram, K.H. Holography, holonomy and brain function. Elsevier's Encyclopedia of Neuroscience, 1999.
- ↑ Jibu, M., Pribrm, K. H., & Yasue, K. (1996). From conscious experience to memory storage and retrieval: The role of quantum brain dynamics and boson condensation of evanescent photons. International Journal of Modern Physics B, 10, 1735-1754.
- ↑ Kak, S. (1995) Quantum neural computing, In Advances in Imaging and Electron Physics, vol. 94, P. Hawkes (editor). Academic Press, 259-313.
- ↑ Kak, S. (1996) The three languages of the brain: quantum, reorganizational, and associative. In Learning as Self- Organization, K. Pribram and J. King (editors). Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Mahwah, NJ, 185-219.
- ↑ Gautam, A. and S. Kak (2013), Symbols, meaning, and origins of mind. Biosemiotics (Springer Verlag) 6: 301-310.
- ↑ Kak, S. (2000), Active agents, intelligence, and quantum computing. Information Sciences 128: 1-17.
- ↑ Kak, S. (2005), Artificial and biological intelligence. ACM Ubiquity 6 (42): 1-22.
- ↑ Bourget, D. (2004). "Quantum Leaps in Philosophy of Mind: A Critique of Stapp's Theory". Journal of Consciousness Studies 11 (12): 17–42.
- 1 2 3 Georgiev, D. (2012). "Mind efforts, quantum Zeno effect and environmental decoherence". NeuroQuantology 10 (3): 374–388. doi:10.14704/nq.2012.10.3.552.
- 1 2 Georgiev, D. (2015). "Monte Carlo simulation of quantum Zeno effect in the brain". International Journal of Modern Physics B 29 (7): 1550039. arXiv:1412.4741. doi:10.1142/S0217979215500393.
- ↑ Tegmark, M. (2000). "Importance of quantum decoherence in brain processes". Physical Review E 61 (4): 4194–4206. arXiv:quant-ph/9907009. Bibcode:2000PhRvE..61.4194T. doi:10.1103/PhysRevE.61.4194.
- ↑ Charles Seife (4 February 2000). "Cold Numbers Unmake the Quantum Mind". Science 287 (5454): 791. doi:10.1126/science.287.5454.791. PMID 10691548.
- ↑ Engel, G. (2007). "Evidence for wavelike energy transfer through quantum coherence in photosynthetic systems". Nature 446 (7137): 782–786. doi:10.1038/nature05678. PMID 17429397.
- ↑ Yen, F. and Gao, T. (2015). "Dielectric Anomaly in Ice near 20 K: Evidence of Macroscopic Quantum Phenomena". Journal of Physical Chemistry Letters (July). doi:10.1021/acs.jpclett.5b00797.
Further reading
- Flanagan, Brian. Are Perceptual Fields Quantum Fields?
- Hodgson, David (1993). The Mind Matters: Consciousness and Choice in a Quantum World. Clarendon Press. ISBN 978-0-19-824068-6.
- Koch, C. and Hepp, K., "Quantum mechanics in the brain", Nature 440, 611 (30 March 2006)
- Litt et al., "Is the Brain a Quantum Computer?", Cognitive Science (2006)
- Lockwood, Michael (1995). Mind, Brain, and the Quantum: The Compound 'I'. Basil Blackwell.
- McFadden, Johnjoe (2000) Quantum Evolution HarperCollins. ISBN 0-00-255948-X; ISBN 0-00-655128-9 . Final chapter on the quantum mind.
- Pharaoh, M.C. (online). Looking to quantum mechanics for a reductive explanation of the noumenon of consciousness Retrieved June.21 2008.
- Schrödinger, Erwin (January 2003). Mind and Matter. Textbook Publishers. ISBN 978-0-7581-1275-0.
- Weyl, Hermann Claus Hugo (1934). Mind and Nature. University of Pennsylvania Press.
- Wigner, Eugene (1981). "Physics and the Explanation of Life". In Lindsay, Robert Bruce. Foundations of Physics 1. Ox Bow Press. pp. 34–35. ISBN 978-0-918024-17-6.
|first2=
missing|last2=
in Editors list (help) - Khoshbin-e-Khoshnazar, M.R. (January 2016). Possible Application of Variational Cluster Expansion in Modeling Correlated Neurons. Journal of Consciousness Exploration & Research Vol.7(1), pp.122-125.
External links
- Center for Consciousness Studies, directed by Stuart Hameroff
- Online papers on consciousness
- Stanford Univ. Encyclopedia of Philosophy critical survey article Harald Altmanspacher (2006) Quantum Approaches to Consciousness
- "What is an Essentially Quantum Mechanical Effect?", Osvaldo Pessoa Jr.
- Quantum-Mind